NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, pio@supremecourt.gov, of any typographical or other formal errors.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
_________________
No. 22鈥611
_________________
KEVIN LINDKE, PETITIONER v. JAMES R. FREED
on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the sixth circuit
[March 15, 2024]
Justice Barrett delivered the opinion of the Court.
Like millions of Americans, James Freed maintained a Facebook account on which he posted about a wide range of topics, including his family and his job. Like most of those Americans, Freed occasionally received unwelcome comments on his posts. In response, Freed took a step familiar to Facebook users: He deleted the comments and blocked those who made them.
For most people with a Facebook account, that would have been the end of it. But Kevin Lindke, one of the unwelcome commenters, sued Freed for violating his right to free speech. Because the First Amendment binds only the government, this claim is a nonstarter if Freed posted as a private citizen. Freed, however, is not only a private citizen but also the city manager of Port Huron, Michigan鈥攁nd while Freed insists that his Facebook account was strictly personal, Lindke argues that Freed acted in his official capacity when he silenced Lindke鈥檚 speech.
When a government official posts about job-related topics on social media, it can be difficult to tell whether the speech is official or private. We hold that such speech is attributable to the State only if the official (1) possessed actual authority to speak on the State鈥檚 behalf, and (2) purported to exercise that authority when he spoke on social media.
I
A
Sometime before 2008, while he was a college student, James Freed created a private Facebook profile that he shared only with 鈥渇riends.鈥 In Facebook lingo, 鈥渇riends鈥 are not necessarily confidants or even real-life acquaintances. Users become 鈥渇riends鈥 when one accepts a 鈥渇riend request鈥 from another; after that, the two can generally see and comment on one another鈥檚 posts and photos. When Freed, an avid Facebook user, began nearing the platform鈥檚 5,000-friend limit, he converted his profile to a public 鈥減age.鈥 This meant that anyone could see and comment on his posts. Freed chose 鈥減ublic figure鈥 for his page鈥檚 category, 鈥淛ames Freed鈥 for its title, and 鈥淛amesRFreed1鈥 as his username. Facebook did not require Freed to satisfy any special criteria either to convert his Facebook profile to a public page or to describe himself as a public figure.
In 2014, Freed was appointed city manager of Port Huron, Michigan, and he updated his Facebook page to reflect the new job. For his profile picture, Freed chose a photo of himself in a suit with a city lapel pin. In the 鈥淎bout鈥 section, Freed added his title, a link to the city鈥檚 website, and the city鈥檚 general email address. He described himself as 鈥淒addy to Lucy, Husband to Jessie and City Manager, Chief Administrative Officer for the citizens of Port Huron, MI.鈥
As before his appointment, Freed operated his Facebook page himself. And, as before his appointment, Freed posted prolifically (and primarily) about his personal life. He uploaded hundreds of photos of his daughter. He shared about outings like the Daddy Daughter Dance, dinner with his wife, and a family nature walk. He posted Bible verses, updates on home-improvement projects, and pictures of his dog, Winston.
Freed also posted information related to his job. He described mundane activities, like visiting local high schools, as well as splashier ones, like starting reconstruction of the city鈥檚 boat launch. He shared news about the city鈥檚 efforts to streamline leaf pickup and stabilize water intake from a local river. He highlighted communications from other city officials, like a press release from the fire chief and an annual financial report from the finance department. On occasion, Freed solicited feedback from the public鈥攆or instance, he once posted a link to a city survey about housing and encouraged his audience to complete it.
Freed鈥檚 readers frequently commented on his posts, sometimes with reactions (for example, 鈥淕ood job it takes skills鈥 on a picture of his sleeping daughter) and sometimes with questions (for example, 鈥淐an you allow city residents to have chickens?鈥). Freed often replied to the comments, including by answering inquiries from city residents. (City residents can have chickens and should 鈥渃all the Planning Dept for details.鈥) He occasionally deleted comments that he thought were 鈥渄erogatory鈥 or 鈥渟tupid.鈥
After the COVID鈥19 pandemic began, Freed posted about that. Some posts were personal, like pictures of his family spending time at home and outdoors to 鈥淸s]tay safe鈥 and 鈥淸s]ave lives.鈥 Some contained general information, like case counts and weekly hospitalization numbers. Others related to Freed鈥檚 job, like a description of the city鈥檚 hiring freeze and a screenshot of a press release about a relief package that he helped prepare.
Enter Kevin Lindke. Unhappy with the city鈥檚 approach to the pandemic, Lindke visited Freed鈥檚 page and said so. For example, in response to one of Freed鈥檚 posts, Lindke commented that the city鈥檚 pandemic response was 鈥渁bysmal鈥 and that 鈥渢he city deserves better.鈥 When Freed posted a photo of himself and the mayor picking up takeout from a local restaurant, Lindke complained that while 鈥渞esidents [we]re suffering,鈥 the city鈥檚 leaders were eating at an expensive restaurant 鈥渋nstead of out talking to the community.鈥 Initially, Freed deleted Lindke鈥檚 comments; ultimately, he blocked him. Once blocked, Lindke could see Freed鈥檚 posts but could no longer comment on them.
B
Lindke sued Freed under 42 U. S. C. 搂1983, alleging that Freed had violated his First Amendment rights. As Lindke saw it, he had the right to comment on Freed鈥檚 Facebook page, which he characterized as a public forum. Freed, Lindke claimed, had engaged in impermissible viewpoint discrimination by deleting unfavorable comments and blocking the people who made them.
The District Court granted summary judgment to Freed. Because only state action can give rise to liability under 搂1983, Lindke鈥檚 claim depended on whether Freed acted in a 鈥減rivate鈥 or 鈥減ublic鈥 capacity. 563 F. Supp. 3d 704, 714 (ED Mich. 2021). The 鈥減revailing personal quality of Freed鈥檚 post[s],鈥 the absence of 鈥済overnment involvement鈥 with his account, and the lack of posts conducting official business led the court to conclude that Freed managed his Facebook page in his private capacity, so Lindke鈥檚 claim failed. Ibid.
The Sixth Circuit affirmed. It noted that 鈥渢he caselaw is murky as to when a state official acts personally and when he acts officially鈥 for purposes of 搂1983. 37 F. 4th 1199, 1202 (2022). To sort the personal from the official, that court 鈥渁sks whether the official is 鈥榩erforming an actual or apparent duty of his office,鈥 or if he could not have behaved as he did 鈥榳ithout the authority of his office.鈥 鈥 Id., at 1203 (quoting Waters v. Morristown, 242 F.3d 353, 359 (CA6 2001)). Applying this precedent to the social-media context, the Sixth Circuit held that an official鈥檚 activity is state action if the 鈥渢ext of state law requires an officeholder to maintain a social-media account,鈥 the official 鈥渦se[s] . . . state resources鈥 or 鈥済overnment staff 鈥 to run the account, or the 鈥渁ccoun[t] belong[s] to an office, rather than an individual officeholder.鈥 37 F. 4th, at 1203鈥1204. These situations, the Sixth Circuit explained, make an official鈥檚 social-media activity 鈥 鈥榝airly attributable鈥 鈥 to the State. Id., at 1204 (quoting Lugar v. Edmondson Oil Co., 457 U.S. 922, 937 (1982)). And it concluded that Freed鈥檚 activity was not.
The Sixth Circuit鈥檚 approach to state action in the social-media context differs from that of the Second and Ninth Circuits, which focus less on the connection between the official鈥檚 authority and the account and more on whether the account鈥檚 appearance and content look official. See, e.g., Garnier v. 翱鈥机辞苍苍辞谤-搁补迟肠濒颈蹿蹿, 41 F. 4th 1158, 1170鈥1171 (CA9 2022); Knight First Amdt. Inst. at Columbia Univ. v. Trump, 928 F.3d 226, 236 (CA2 2019), vacated as moot sub nom. Biden v. Knight First Amdt. Inst. at Columbia Univ., 593 U. S. ___ (2021). We granted certiorari. 598 U. S. ___ (2023).
II
Section 1983 provides a cause of action against 鈥淸e]very person who, under color of any statute, ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage, of any State鈥 deprives someone of a federal constitutional or statutory right. (Emphasis added.) As its text makes clear, this provision protects against acts attributable to a State, not those of a private person. This limit tracks that of the Fourteenth Amendment, which obligates States to honor the constitutional rights that 搂1983 protects. 搂1 (鈥淣o State shall . . . nor shall any State deprive . . . 鈥 (emphasis added)); see also Lugar, 457 U. S., at 929 (鈥淸T]he statutory requirement of action 鈥榰nder color of state law鈥 and the 鈥榮tate action鈥 requirement of the Fourteenth Amendment are identical鈥). The need for governmental action is also explicit in the Free Speech Clause, the guarantee that Lindke invokes in this case. Amdt. 1 (鈥Congress shall make no law . . . abridging the freedom of speech . . . 鈥 (emphasis added)); see also Manhattan Community Access Corp. v. Halleck, 587 U.S. 802, 808 (2019) (鈥淸T]he Free Speech Clause prohibits only governmental abridgment of speech,鈥 not 鈥private abridgment of speech鈥). In short, the state-action requirement is both well established and reinforced by multiple sources.[]
In the run-of-the-mill case, state action is easy to spot. Courts do not ordinarily pause to consider whether 搂1983 applies to the actions of police officers, public schools, or prison officials. See, e.g., Graham v. Connor, 490 U.S. 386, 388 (1989) (police officers); Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist., 393 U.S. 503, 504鈥505 (1969) (public schools); Estelle v. Gamble, 429 U.S. 97, 98 (1976) (prison officials). And, absent some very unusual facts, no one would credit a child鈥檚 assertion of free speech rights against a parent, or a plaintiff 鈥檚 complaint that a nosy neighbor unlawfully searched his garage.
Sometimes, however, the line between private conduct and state action is difficult to draw. Griffin v. Maryland is a good example. 378 U.S. 130 (1964). There, we held that a security guard at a privately owned amusement park engaged in state action when he enforced the park鈥檚 policy of segregation against black protesters. Id., at 132鈥135. Though employed by the park, the guard had been 鈥渄eputized as a sheriff of Montgomery County鈥 and possessed 鈥 鈥榯he same power and authority鈥 鈥 as any other deputy sheriff. Id., at 132, and n. 1. The State had therefore allowed its power to be exercised by someone in the private sector. And the source of the power, not the identity of the employer, controlled.
By and large, our state-action precedents have grappled with variations of the question posed in Griffin: whether a nominally private person has engaged in state action for purposes of 搂1983. See, e.g., Marsh v. Alabama, 326 U.S. 501, 502鈥503 (1946) (company town); Adickes v. S. H. Kress & Co., 398 U.S. 144, 146鈥147 (1970) (restaurant); Flagg Bros., Inc. v. Brooks, 436 U.S. 149, 151鈥152 (1978) (warehouse company). Today鈥檚 case, by contrast, requires us to analyze whether a state official engaged in state action or functioned as a private citizen. This Court has had little occasion to consider how the state-action requirement applies in this circumstance.
The question is difficult, especially in a case involving a state or local official who routinely interacts with the public. Such officials may look like they are always on the clock, making it tempting to characterize every encounter as part of the job. But the state-action doctrine avoids such broad-brush assumptions鈥攆or good reason. While public officials can act on behalf of the State, they are also private citizens with their own constitutional rights. By excluding from liability 鈥渁cts of officers in the ambit of their personal pursuits,鈥 Screws v. United States, 325 U.S. 91, 111 (1945) (plurality opinion), the state-action requirement 鈥減rotects a robust sphere of individual liberty鈥 for those who serve as public officials or employees, Halleck, 587 U. S., at 808.
The dispute between Lindke and Freed illustrates this dynamic. Freed did not relinquish his First Amendment rights when he became city manager. On the contrary, 鈥渢he First Amendment protects a public employee鈥檚 right, in certain circumstances, to speak as a citizen addressing matters of public concern.鈥 Garcetti v. Ceballos, 547 U.S. 410, 417 (2006). This right includes the ability to speak about 鈥渋nformation related to or learned through public employment,鈥 so long as the speech is not 鈥渋tself ordinarily within the scope of [the] employee鈥檚 duties.鈥 Lane v. Franks, 573 U.S. 228, 236, 240 (2014). Where the right exists, 鈥渆ditorial control over speech and speakers on [the public employee鈥檚] properties or platforms鈥 is part and parcel of it. Halleck, 587 U. S., at 816. Thus, if Freed acted in his private capacity when he blocked Lindke and deleted his comments, he did not violate Lindke鈥檚 First Amendment rights鈥攊nstead, he exercised his own.
So Lindke cannot hang his hat on Freed鈥檚 status as a state employee. The distinction between private conduct and state action turns on substance, not labels: Private parties can act with the authority of the State, and state officials have private lives and their own constitutional rights. Categorizing conduct, therefore, can require a close look.
III
A close look is definitely necessary in the context of a public official using social media. There are approximately 20 million state and local government employees across the Nation, with an extraordinarily wide range of job descriptions鈥攆rom Governors, mayors, and police chiefs to teachers, healthcare professionals, and transportation workers. Many use social media for personal communication, official communication, or both鈥攁nd the line between the two is often blurred. Moreover, social media involves a variety of different and rapidly changing platforms, each with distinct features for speaking, viewing, and removing speech. The Court has frequently emphasized that the state-action doctrine demands a fact-intensive inquiry. See, e.g., Reitman v. Mulkey, 387 U.S. 369, 378 (1967); Gilmore v. Montgomery, 417 U.S. 556, 574 (1974). We repeat that caution here.
That said, our precedent articulates principles that govern cases analogous to this one. For the reasons we explain below, a public official鈥檚 social-media activity constitutes state action under 搂1983 only if the official (1) possessed actual authority to speak on the State鈥檚 behalf, and (2) purported to exercise that authority when he spoke on social media. The appearance and function of the social-media activity are relevant at the second step, but they cannot make up for a lack of state authority at the first.
A
The first prong of this test is grounded in the bedrock requirement that 鈥渢he conduct allegedly causing the deprivation of a federal right be fairly attributable to the State.鈥 Lugar, 457 U. S., at 937 (emphasis added). An act is not attributable to a State unless it is traceable to the State鈥檚 power or authority. Private action鈥攏o matter how 鈥渙fficial鈥 it looks鈥攍acks the necessary lineage.
This rule runs through our cases. Griffin stresses that the security guard was 鈥減ossessed of state authority鈥 and 鈥減urport[ed] to act under that authority.鈥 378 U. S., at 135. West v. Atkins states that the 鈥渢raditional definition鈥 of state action 鈥渞equires that the defendant . . . have exercised power 鈥榩ossessed by virtue of state law and made possible only because the wrongdoer is clothed with the authority of state law.鈥 鈥 487 U.S. 42, 49 (1988) (quoting United States v. Classic, 313 U.S. 299, 326 (1941)). Lugar emphasizes that state action exists only when 鈥渢he claimed deprivation has resulted from the exercise of a right or privilege having its source in state authority.鈥 457 U. S., at 939; see also, e.g., Edmonson v. Leesville Concrete Co., 500 U.S. 614, 620 (1991) (describing state action as the 鈥渆xercise of a right or privilege having its source in state authority鈥); Screws, 325 U. S., at 111 (plurality opinion) (police-officer defendants 鈥渨ere authorized to make an arrest and to take such steps as were necessary to make the arrest effective鈥). By contrast, when the challenged conduct 鈥渆ntail[s] functions and obligations in no way dependent on state authority,鈥 state action does not exist. Polk County v. Dodson, 454 U.S. 312, 318鈥319 (1981) (no state action because criminal defense 鈥渋s essentially a private function . . . for which state office and authority are not needed鈥); see also Jackson v. Metropolitan Edison Co., 419 U.S. 345, 358鈥359 (1974).
Lindke鈥檚 focus on appearance skips over this crucial step. He insists that Freed鈥檚 social-media activity constitutes state action because Freed鈥檚 Facebook page looks and functions like an outlet for city updates and citizen concerns. But Freed鈥檚 conduct is not attributable to the State unless he was 鈥減ossessed of state authority鈥 to post city updates and register citizen concerns. Griffin, 378 U. S., at 135. If the State did not entrust Freed with these responsibilities, it cannot 鈥渇airly be blamed鈥 for the way he discharged them. Lugar, 457 U. S., at 936. Lindke imagines that Freed can conjure the power of the State through his own efforts. Yet the presence of state authority must be real, not a mirage.
Importantly, Lindke must show more than that Freed had some authority to communicate with residents on behalf of Port Huron. The alleged censorship must be connected to speech on a matter within Freed鈥檚 bailiwick. For example, imagine that Freed posted a list of local restaurants with health-code violations and deleted snarky comments made by other users. If public health is not within the portfolio of the city manager, then neither the post nor the deletions would be traceable to Freed鈥檚 state authority鈥攂ecause he had none. For state action to exist, the State must be 鈥渞esponsible for the specific conduct of which the plaintiff complains.鈥 Blum v. Yaretsky, 457 U.S. 991, 1004 (1982) (emphasis deleted). There must be a tie between the official鈥檚 authority and 鈥渢he gravamen of the plaintiff 鈥檚 complaint.鈥 Id., at 1003.
To be clear, the 鈥淸m]isuse of power, possessed by virtue of state law,鈥 constitutes state action. Classic, 313 U. S., at 326 (emphasis added); see also, e.g., Screws, 325 U. S., at 110 (plurality opinion) (state action where 鈥渢he power which [state officers] were authorized to exercise was misused鈥). While the state-action doctrine requires that the State have granted an official the type of authority that he used to violate rights鈥e.g., the power to arrest鈥攊t encompasses cases where his 鈥減articular action鈥濃e.g., an arrest made with excessive force鈥攙iolated state or federal law. Griffin, 378 U. S., at 135; see also Home Telephone & Telegraph Co. v. Los Angeles, 227 U.S. 278, 287鈥288 (1913) (the Fourteenth Amendment encompasses 鈥渁buse by a state officer . . . of the powers possessed鈥). Every 搂1983 suit alleges a misuse of power, because no state actor has the authority to deprive someone of a federal right. To misuse power, however, one must possess it in the first place.
Where does the power come from? Section 1983 lists the potential sources: 鈥渟tatute, ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage.鈥 Statutes, ordinances, and regulations refer to written law through which a State can authorize an official to speak on its behalf. 鈥淐ustom鈥 and 鈥渦sage鈥 encompass 鈥減ersistent practices of state officials鈥 that are 鈥渟o permanent and well settled鈥 that they carry 鈥渢he force of law.鈥 Adickes, 398 U. S., at 167鈥168. So a city manager like Freed would be authorized to speak for the city if written law like an ordinance empowered him to make official announcements. He would also have that authority even in the absence of written law if, for instance, prior city managers have purported to speak on its behalf and have been recognized to have that authority for so long that the manager鈥檚 power to do so has become 鈥減ermanent and well settled.鈥 Id., at 168. And if an official has authority to speak for the State, he may have the authority to do so on social media even if the law does not make that explicit.
Determining the scope of an official鈥檚 power requires careful attention to the relevant statute, ordinance, regulation, custom, or usage. In some cases, a grant of authority over particular subject matter may reasonably encompass authority to speak about it officially. For example, state law might grant a high-ranking official like the director of the state department of transportation broad responsibility for the state highway system that, in context, includes authority to make official announcements on that subject. At the same time, courts must not rely on 鈥 鈥榚xcessively broad job descriptions鈥 鈥 to conclude that a government employee is authorized to speak for the State. Kennedy v. Bremerton School Dist., 597 U.S. 507, 529 (2022) (quoting Garcetti, 547 U. S., at 424). The inquiry is not whether making official announcements could fit within the job description; it is whether making official announcements is actually part of the job that the State entrusted the official to do.
In sum, a defendant like Freed must have actual authority rooted in written law or longstanding custom to speak for the State. That authority must extend to speech of the sort that caused the alleged rights deprivation. If the plaintiff cannot make this threshold showing of authority, he cannot establish state action.
B
For social-media activity to constitute state action, an official must not only have state authority鈥攈e must also purport to use it. Griffin, 378 U. S., at 135. State officials have a choice about the capacity in which they choose to speak. 鈥淸G]enerally, a public employee鈥 purports to speak on behalf of the State while speaking 鈥渋n his official capacity or鈥 when he uses his speech to fulfill 鈥渉is responsibilities pursuant to state law.鈥 West, 487 U. S., at 50. If the public employee does not use his speech in furtherance of his official responsibilities, he is speaking in his own voice.
Consider a hypothetical from the offline world. A school board president announces at a school board meeting that the board has lifted pandemic-era restrictions on public schools. The next evening, at a backyard barbecue with friends whose children attend public schools, he shares that the board has lifted the pandemic-era restrictions. The former is state action taken in his official capacity as school board president; the latter is private action taken in his personal capacity as a friend and neighbor. While the substance of the announcement is the same, the context鈥攁n official meeting versus a private event鈥攄iffers. He invoked his official authority only when he acted as school board president.
The context of Freed鈥檚 speech is hazier than that of the hypothetical school board president. Had Freed鈥檚 account carried a label (e.g., 鈥渢his is the personal page of James R. Freed鈥) or a disclaimer (e.g., 鈥渢he views expressed are strictly my own鈥), he would be entitled to a heavy (though not irrebuttable) presumption that all of the posts on his page were personal. Markers like these give speech the benefit of clear context: Just as we can safely presume that speech at a backyard barbeque is personal, we can safely presume that speech on a 鈥減ersonal鈥 page is personal (absent significant evidence indicating that a post is official).[] Conversely, context can make clear that a social-media account purports to speak for the government鈥攆or instance, when an account belongs to a political subdivision (e.g., a 鈥淐ity of Port Huron鈥 Facebook page) or is passed down to whomever occupies a particular office (e.g., an 鈥淍PHuronCityMgr鈥 Instagram account). Freed鈥檚 page, however, was not designated either 鈥減ersonal鈥 or 鈥渙fficial,鈥 raising the prospect that it was 鈥渕ixed use鈥濃攁 place where he made some posts in his personal capacity and others in his capacity as city manager.
Categorizing posts that appear on an ambiguous page like Freed鈥檚 is a fact-specific undertaking in which the post鈥檚 content and function are the most important considerations. In some circumstances, the post鈥檚 content and function might make the plaintiff 鈥檚 argument a slam dunk. Take a mayor who makes the following announcement exclusively on his Facebook page: 鈥淧ursuant to Municipal Ordinance 22.1, I am temporarily suspending enforcement of alternate-side parking rules.鈥 The post鈥檚 express invocation of state authority, its immediate legal effect, and the fact that the order is not available elsewhere make clear that the mayor is purporting to discharge an official duty. If, by contrast, the mayor merely repeats or shares otherwise available information鈥攆or example, by linking to the parking announcement on the city鈥檚 webpage鈥攊t is far less likely that he is purporting to exercise the power of his office. Instead, it is much more likely that he is engaging in private speech 鈥渞elate[d] to his public employment鈥 or 鈥渃oncern[ing] information learned during that employment.鈥 Lane, 573 U. S., at 238.
Hard-to-classify cases require awareness that an official does not necessarily purport to exercise his authority simply by posting about a matter within it. He might post job-related information for any number of personal reasons, from a desire to raise public awareness to promoting his prospects for reelection. Moreover, many public officials possess a broad portfolio of governmental authority that includes routine interaction with the public, and it may not be easy to discern a boundary between their public and private lives. Yet these officials too have the right to speak about public affairs in their personal capacities. See, e.g., id., at 235鈥236. Lest any official lose that right, it is crucial for the plaintiff to show that the official is purporting to exercise state authority in specific posts. And when there is doubt, additional factors might cast light鈥攆or example, an official who uses government staff to make a post will be hard pressed to deny that he was conducting government business.
One last point: The nature of the technology matters to the state-action analysis. Freed performed two actions to which Lindke objected: He deleted Lindke鈥檚 comments and blocked him from commenting again. So far as deletion goes, the only relevant posts are those from which Lindke鈥檚 comments were removed. Blocking, however, is a different story. Because blocking operated on a page-wide basis, a court would have to consider whether Freed had engaged in state action with respect to any post on which Lindke wished to comment. The bluntness of Facebook鈥檚 blocking tool highlights the cost of a 鈥渕ixed use鈥 social-media account: If page-wide blocking is the only option, a public official might be unable to prevent someone from commenting on his personal posts without risking liability for also preventing comments on his official posts.[] A public official who fails to keep personal posts in a clearly designated personal account therefore exposes himself to greater potential liability.
*鈥冣赌*鈥冣赌*
The state-action doctrine requires Lindke to show that Freed (1) had actual authority to speak on behalf of the State on a particular matter, and (2) purported to exercise that authority in the relevant posts. To the extent that this test differs from the one applied by the Sixth Circuit, we vacate its judgment and remand the case for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.
It is so ordered.
Notes
Because local governments are subdivisions of the State, actions taken under color of a local government鈥檚 law, custom, or usage count as 鈥渟tate鈥 action for purposes of 搂1983. See Monell v. New York City Dept. of Social Servs., 436 U.S. 658, 690鈥691 (1978). And when a state or municipal employee violates a federal right while acting 鈥渦nder color of law,鈥 he can be sued in an individual capacity, as Freed was here.
An official cannot insulate government business from scrutiny by conducting it on a personal page. The Solicitor General offers the particularly clear example of an official who designates space on his nominally personal page as the official channel for receiving comments on a proposed regulation. Because the power to conduct notice-and-comment rulemaking belongs exclusively to the State, its exercise is necessarily governmental. Similarly, a mayor would engage in state action if he hosted a city council meeting online by streaming it only on his personalFacebook page. By contrast, a post that is compatible with either a 鈥減ersonal capacity鈥 or 鈥渙fficial capacity鈥 designation is 鈥減ersonal鈥 if it appears on a personal page.
On some platforms, a blocked user might be unable even to see the blocker鈥檚 posts. See, e.g., Garnier v. 翱鈥机辞苍苍辞谤-搁补迟肠濒颈蹿蹿, 41 F. 4th, 1158, 1164 (CA9 2022) (noting that 鈥渙n Twitter, once a user has been 鈥榖locked,鈥 the individual can neither interact with nor view the blocker鈥檚 Twitter feed鈥); Knight First Amdt. Inst. at Columbia Univ. v. Trump, 928 F.3d 226, 231 (CA2 2019) (noting that a blocked user is unable to see, reply to, retweet, or like the blocker鈥檚 tweets).