果冻传媒app官方

Opinions

Majority Opinion Author

Elena Kagan

DOWNLOAD JACK DANIELS PROPERTIES, INC. v. VIP PRODUCTS LLC DECISION

NOTE:鈥俉here it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U.S. 321, 337.

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

Syllabus

JACK DANIEL鈥橲 PROPERTIES, INC. v. VIP PRODUCTS LLC

certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit

No. 22鈥148.鈥傾rgued March 22, 2023鈥擠ecided June 8, 2023

The Lanham Act, the core federal trademark statute, defines a trademark by its primary function: identifying a product鈥檚 source and distinguishing that source from others. In serving that function, trademarks help consumers select the products they want to purchase (or avoid) and help producers reap the financial rewards associated with a product鈥檚 good reputation. To help protect trademarks, the Lanham Act creates federal causes of action for trademark infringement and trademark dilution. In a typical infringement case, the question is whether the defendant鈥檚 use of a mark is 鈥渓ikely to cause confusion, or to cause mistake, or to deceive.鈥 15 U. S. C. 搂搂1114(1)(A), 1125(a)(1)(A). In a typical dilution case, the question is whether the defendant 鈥渉arm[ed] the reputation鈥 of a famous trademark. 搂搂1125(c)(2)(A), (C).

Respondent VIP Products makes a squeaky, chewable dog toy designed to look like a bottle of Jack Daniel鈥檚 whiskey. But not entirely. On the toy, for example, the words 鈥淛ack Daniel鈥檚鈥 become 鈥淏ad Spaniels.鈥 And 鈥淥ld No. 7 Brand Tennessee Sour Mash Whiskey鈥 turns into 鈥淭he Old No. 2 On Your Tennessee Carpet.鈥 These jokes did not impress petitioner Jack Daniel鈥檚 Properties, which owns trademarks in the distinctive Jack Daniel鈥檚 bottle and in many of the words and graphics on its label.

Soon after the Bad Spaniels toy hit the market, Jack Daniel鈥檚 demanded that VIP stop selling it. VIP filed suit, seeking a declaratory judgment that Bad Spaniels neither infringed nor diluted Jack Daniel鈥檚 trademarks. Jack Daniel鈥檚 counterclaimed for infringement and dilution. At summary judgment, VIP argued that Jack Daniel鈥檚 infringement claim failed under the so-called Rogers test鈥攁 threshold test developed by the Second Circuit and designed to protect First Amendment interests in the trademark context. See Rogers v. Grimaldi, 875 F.2d 994. When 鈥渆xpressive works鈥 are involved, VIP contended, that test requires dismissal of an infringement claim at the outset unless the complainant can show either (1) that the challenged use of a mark 鈥渉as no artistic relevance to the underlying work鈥 or (2) that it 鈥渆xplicitly misleads as to the source or the content of the work.鈥 Id., at 999. Because Jack Daniel鈥檚 could not make that showing, VIP claimed, the Lanham Act鈥檚 statutory 鈥渓ikelihood of confusion鈥 standard became irrelevant. And as for the dilution claim, VIP urged that Jack Daniel鈥檚 could not succeed because Bad Spaniels was a parody of Jack Daniel鈥檚 and therefore made 鈥渇air use鈥 of its famous marks. 搂1125(c)(3)(A)(ii).

The District Court rejected both of VIP鈥檚 contentions for a common reason: because VIP had used the cribbed Jack Daniel鈥檚 features as trademarks鈥i.e., to identify the source of its own products. As the District Court saw it, when another鈥檚 trademark is used for 鈥渟ource identification,鈥 Rogers does not apply, and instead the infringement suit turns on likelihood of confusion. The court likewise rejected VIP鈥檚 invocation of the fair-use exclusion, holding that parodies fall within that exclusion only when they do not use a famous mark to identify the source of the alleged diluter鈥檚 product. The case proceeded to a bench trial, where the District Court found that consumers were likely to be confused about the source of the Bad Spaniels toy and that the toy鈥檚 negative associations with dog excrement (e.g., 鈥淭he Old No. 2鈥) would harm Jack Daniel鈥檚 reputation. The Ninth Circuit reversed. Finding the infringement claim subject to the threshold Rogers test, the Court of Appeals remanded the case to the District Court to decide whether Jack Daniel鈥檚 could satisfy either prong of that test. And the Court of Appeals awarded judgment on the dilution claim to VIP, holding that because Bad Spaniels parodies Jack Daniel鈥檚, it falls under the 鈥渘oncommercial use鈥 exclusion. 搂1125(c)(3)(C). On remand, the District Court found that Jack Daniel鈥檚 could not satisfy either prong of Rogers, and so granted summary judgment to VIP on infringement. The Court of Appeals summarily affirmed.

Held

1. When an alleged infringer uses a trademark as a designation of source for the infringer鈥檚 own goods, the Rogers test does not apply. Pp. 10鈥19.

(a) The Second Circuit created the Rogers test for titles of 鈥渁rtistic works鈥 based on its view that such titles have an 鈥渆xpressive element鈥 implicating 鈥 First Amendment values鈥 and carry only a 鈥渟light risk鈥 of confusing consumers about the 鈥渟ource or content鈥 of the underlying work. 875 F. 2d, at 998鈥1000. Over the decades, lower courts adopting Rogers have confined it to similar cases, in which a trademark is used not to designate a work鈥檚 source, but solely to perform some other expressive function. See, e.g., Mattel, Inc. v. MCA Records, Inc., 296 F.3d 894, 901 (use of the Barbie name in band鈥檚 song 鈥淏arbie Girl鈥 was 鈥渘ot [as] a source identifier鈥). The same courts, though, routinely conduct likelihood-of-confusion analysis in cases where trademarks are used as trademarks鈥i.e., to designate source. See, e.g., Tommy Hilfiger Licensing, Inc. v. Nature Labs, LLC, 221 F. Supp. 2d 410, 414鈥415 (parodic pet perfumes did not trigger Rogers because defendant鈥檚 use of Tommy Hilfiger鈥檚 mark was 鈥渁t least in part鈥 for 鈥渟ource identification鈥). Thus, whatever Rogers鈥 merit鈥攁n issue on which this Court takes no position鈥攊t has always been a cabined doctrine: It has not insulated from ordinary trademark scrutiny the use of trademarks as trademarks.

That conclusion fits trademark law, and reflects its primary mission. Consumer confusion about source鈥攖rademark law鈥檚 cardinal sin鈥攊s most likely to arise when someone uses another鈥檚 trademark as a trademark. In such cases, Rogers has no proper application. Nor does that result change because the use of a mark has other expressive content. Under the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 approach, Bad Spaniels was automatically entitled to Rogers鈥 protection because it 鈥渃ommunicate[d] a humorous message.鈥 953 F.3d 1170, 1175. On that view, few trademark cases would ever get to the likelihood-of-confusion analysis. And the Ninth Circuit was mistaken to believe that the First Amendment demanded such a result. When a mark is used as a source identifier, the First Amendment does not demand a threshold inquiry. Pp. 10鈥17.

(b) In this case, VIP conceded that it used the Bad Spaniels trademark and trade dress as source identifiers. And VIP has said and done more in the same direction with respect to Bad Spaniels and other similar products. The only question remaining is whether the Bad Spaniels trademarks are likely to cause confusion. Although VIP鈥檚 effort to parody Jack Daniel鈥檚 does not justify use of the Rogers test, it may make a difference in the standard trademark analysis. This Court remands that issue to the courts below. Pp. 17鈥19.

2. The Lanham Act鈥檚 exclusion from dilution liability for 鈥淸a]ny noncommerical use of a mark,鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(C), does not shield parody, criticism, or commentary when an alleged diluter uses a mark as a designation of source for its own goods. The Ninth Circuit鈥檚 holding to the contrary puts the noncommercial exclusion in conflict with the statute鈥檚 fair-use exclusion. The latter exclusion specifically covers uses 鈥減arodying, criticizing, or commenting upon鈥 a famous mark owner, 搂1125(c)(3)(A)(ii), but does not apply when the use is 鈥渁s a designation of source for the person鈥檚 own goods or services,鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(A). Given that carve-out, parody is exempt from liability only if not used to designate source. The Ninth Circuit鈥檚 expansive view of the noncommercial use exclusion鈥攖hat parody is always exempt, regardless whether it designates source鈥攅ffectively nullifies Congress鈥檚 express limit on the fair-use exclusion for parody. Pp. 19鈥20.

953 F.3d 1170, vacated and remanded.

Kagan, J., delivered the opinion for a unanimous Court. Sotomayor, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which Alito, J., joined. Gorsuch, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which Thomas and Barrett, JJ., joined.


SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

No. 22鈥148

JACK DANIEL鈥橲 PROPERTIES, INC., PETITIONER v. VIP PRODUCTS LLC

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit

[June 8, 2023]

Justice Kagan delivered the opinion of the Court.

This case is about dog toys and whiskey, two items seldom appearing in the same sentence. Respondent VIP Products makes a squeaky, chewable dog toy designed to look like a bottle of Jack Daniel鈥檚 whiskey. Though not entirely. On the toy, for example, the words 鈥淛ack Daniel鈥檚鈥 become 鈥淏ad Spaniels.鈥 And the descriptive phrase 鈥淥ld No. 7 Brand Tennessee Sour Mash Whiskey鈥 turns into 鈥淭he Old No. 2 On Your Tennessee Carpet.鈥 The jokes did not impress petitioner Jack Daniel鈥檚 Properties. It owns trademarks in the distinctive Jack Daniel鈥檚 bottle and in many of the words and graphics on the label. And it believed Bad Spaniels had both infringed and diluted those trademarks. Bad Spaniels had infringed the marks, the argument ran, by leading consumers to think that Jack Daniel鈥檚 had created, or was otherwise responsible for, the dog toy. And Bad Spaniels had diluted the marks, the argument went on, by associating the famed whiskey with, well, dog excrement.

The Court of Appeals, in the decision we review, saw things differently. Though the federal trademark statute makes infringement turn on the likelihood of consumer confusion, the Court of Appeals never got to that issue. On the court鈥檚 view, the First Amendment compels a stringent threshold test when an infringement suit challenges a so-called expressive work鈥攈ere (so said the court), the Bad Spaniels toy. And that test knocked out Jack Daniel鈥檚 claim, whatever the likelihood of confusion. Likewise, Jack鈥檚 dilution claim failed鈥攖hough on that issue the problem was statutory. The trademark law provides that the 鈥渘oncommercial鈥 use of a mark cannot count as dilution. 15 U. S. C. 搂1125(c)(3)(C). The Bad Spaniels marks, the court held, fell within that exemption because the toy communicated a message鈥攁 kind of parody鈥攁bout Jack Daniel鈥檚.

Today, we reject both conclusions. The infringement issue is the more substantial. In addressing it, we do not decide whether the threshold inquiry applied in the Court of Appeals is ever warranted. We hold only that it is not appropriate when the accused infringer has used a trademark to designate the source of its own goods鈥攊n other words, has used a trademark as a trademark. That kind of use falls within the heartland of trademark law, and does not receive special First Amendment protection. The dilution issue is more simply addressed. The use of a mark does not count as noncommercial just because it parodies, or otherwise comments on, another鈥檚 products.

I

A

Start at square 1, with what a trademark is and does. The Lanham Act, the core federal trademark statute, defines a trademark as follows: 鈥淸A]ny word, name, symbol, or device, or any combination thereof 鈥 that a person uses 鈥渢o identify and distinguish his or her goods . . . from those manufactured or sold by others and to indicate the source of the goods.鈥 搂1127. The first part of that definition, identifying the kind of things covered, is broad: It encompasses words (think 鈥淕oogle鈥), graphic designs (Nike鈥檚 swoosh), and so-called trade dress, the overall appearance of a product and its packaging (a Hershey鈥檚 Kiss, in its silver wrapper). See Wal-Mart Stores, Inc. v. Samara Brothers, Inc., 529 U.S. 205, 209鈥210 (2000). The second part of the definition describes every trademark鈥檚 鈥減rimary鈥 function: 鈥渢o identify the origin or ownership of the article to which it is affixed.鈥 Hanover Star Milling Co. v. Metcalf, 240 U.S. 403, 412 (1916). Trademarks can of course do other things: catch a consumer鈥檚 eye, appeal to his fancies, and convey every manner of message. But whatever else it may do, a trademark is not a trademark unless it identifies a product鈥檚 source (this is a Nike) and distinguishes that source from others (not any other sneaker brand). See generally 1 J. McCarthy, Trademarks and Unfair Competition 搂3:1 (5th ed. 2023). In other words, a mark tells the public who is responsible for a product.

In serving that function, trademarks benefit consumers and producers alike. A source-identifying mark enables customers to select 鈥渢he goods and services that they wish to purchase, as well as those they want to avoid.鈥 Matal v. Tam, 582 U.S. 218, 224 (2017). The mark 鈥渜uickly and easily assures a potential customer that this item鈥攖he item with this mark鈥攊s made by the same producer as other similarly marked items that he or she liked (or disliked) in the past.鈥 Qualitex Co. v. Jacobson Products Co., 514 U.S. 159, 164 (1995). And because that is so, the producer of a quality product may derive significant value from its marks. They ensure that the producer itself鈥攁nd not some 鈥渋mitating competitor鈥濃攚ill reap the financial rewards associated with the product鈥檚 good reputation. Ibid.

To help protect marks, the Lanham Act sets up a voluntary registration system. Any mark owner may apply to the Patent and Trademark Office to get its mark placed on a federal register. Consistent with trademark law鈥檚 basic purpose, the lead criterion for registration is that the mark 鈥渋n fact serve as a 鈥榯rademark鈥 to identify and distinguish goods.鈥 3 McCarthy 搂19:10 (listing the principal register鈥檚 eligibility standards). If it does, and the statute鈥檚 other criteria also are met, the registering trademark owner receives certain benefits, useful in infringement litigation. See, e.g., Iancu v. Brunetti, 588 U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (slip op., at 2) (noting that 鈥渞egistration constitutes 鈥榩rima facie evidence鈥 of the mark鈥檚 validity鈥). But the owner of even an unregistered trademark can 鈥渦se [the mark] in commerce and enforce it against infringers.鈥 Ibid.

The Lanham Act also creates a federal cause of action for trademark infringement. In the typical case, the owner of a mark sues someone using a mark that closely resembles its own. The court must decide whether the defendant鈥檚 use is 鈥渓ikely to cause confusion, or to cause mistake, or to deceive.鈥 搂搂1114(1)(A), 1125(a)(1)(A). The 鈥渒eystone鈥 in that statutory standard is 鈥渓ikelihood of confusion.鈥 See 4 McCarthy 搂23:1. And the single type of confusion most commonly in trademark law鈥檚 sights is confusion 鈥渁bout the source of a product or service.鈥 Moseley v. V Secret Catalogue, Inc., 537 U.S. 418, 428 (2003); see 4 McCarthy 搂23:5. Confusion as to source is the b锚te noire of trademark law鈥攖he thing that stands directly opposed to the law鈥檚 twin goals of facilitating consumers鈥 choice and protecting producers鈥 good will.

Finally, the Lanham Act creates a cause of action for the dilution of famous marks, which can succeed without likelihood of confusion. See 搂1125(c); Moseley, 537 U. S., at 431. A famous mark is one 鈥渨idely recognized鈥 by the public as 鈥渄esignati[ng the] source鈥 of the mark owner鈥檚 goods. 搂1125(c)(2)(A). Dilution of such a mark can occur 鈥渂y tarnishment鈥 (as well as by 鈥渂lurring,鈥 not relevant here). 搂1125(c)(1). As the statute describes the idea, an 鈥渁ssociation arising from the similarity between鈥 two marks鈥攐ne of them famous鈥攎ay 鈥渉arm[ ] the reputation of the famous mark,鈥 and thus make the other mark鈥檚 owner liable. 搂1125(c)(2)(C). But there are 鈥淸e]xclusions鈥濃攃ategories of activity not 鈥渁ctionable as dilution.鈥 搂1125(c)(3). One exclusion protects any 鈥渘oncommercial use of a mark.鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(C). Another protects a 鈥渇air use鈥 of a mark 鈥渋n connection with . . . parodying, criticizing, or commenting upon the famous mark owner or [its] goods.鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(A)(ii). The fair-use exclusion, though, comes with a caveat. A defendant cannot get its benefit鈥攅ven if engaging in parody, criticism, or commentary鈥攚hen using the similar-looking mark 鈥渁s a designation of source for the [defendant鈥檚] own goods.鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(A). In other words, the exclusion does not apply if the defendant uses the similar mark as a mark.

B

A bottle of Jack Daniel鈥檚鈥攏o, Jack Daniel鈥檚 Old No. 7 Tennessee Sour Mash Whiskey鈥攂oasts a fair number of trademarks. Recall what the bottle looks like (or better yet, retrieve a bottle from wherever you keep liquor; it鈥檚 probably there):

鈥淛ack Daniel鈥檚鈥 is a registered trademark, as is 鈥淥ld No. 7.鈥 So too the arched Jack Daniel鈥檚 logo. And the stylized label with filigree (i.e., twirling white lines). Finally, what might be thought of as the platform for all those marks鈥攖he whiskey鈥檚 distinctive square bottle鈥攊s itself registered.

VIP is a dog toy company, making and selling a product line of chewable rubber toys that it calls 鈥淪illy Squeakers.鈥 (Yes, they squeak when bitten.) Most of the toys in the line are designed to look like鈥攁nd to parody鈥攑opular beverage brands. There are, to take a sampling, Dos Perros (cf. Dos Equis), Smella Arpaw (cf. Stella Artois), and Doggie Walker (cf. Johnnie Walker). VIP has registered trademarks in all those names, as in the umbrella term 鈥淪illy Squeakers.鈥

In 2014, VIP added the Bad Spaniels toy to the line. VIP did not apply to register the name, or any other feature of, Bad Spaniels. But according to its complaint (further addressed below), VIP both 鈥渙wn[s]鈥 and 鈥渦se[s]鈥 the 鈥 鈥楤ad Spaniels鈥 trademark and trade dress.鈥 App. 3, 11; see infra, at 8, 17. And Bad Spaniels鈥 trade dress, like the dress of many Silly Squeakers toys, is designed to evoke a distinctive beverage bottle-with-label. Even if you didn鈥檛 already know, you鈥檇 probably not have much trouble identifying which one.

Bad Spaniels is about the same size and shape as an ordinary bottle of Jack Daniel鈥檚. The faux bottle, like the original, has a black label with stylized white text and a white filigreed border. The words 鈥淏ad Spaniels鈥 replace 鈥淛ack Daniel鈥檚鈥 in a like font and arch. Above the arch is an image of a spaniel. (This is a dog toy, after all.) Below the arch, 鈥淭he Old No. 2 On Your Tennessee Carpet鈥 replaces 鈥淥ld No. 7 Tennessee Sour Mash Whiskey鈥 in similar graphic form. The small print at the bottom substitutes 鈥43% poo by vol.鈥 and 鈥100% smelly鈥 for 鈥40% alc. by vol. (80 proof ).鈥

The toy is packaged for sale with a cardboard hangtag (so it can be hung on store shelves). Here is the back of the hangtag:

At the bottom is a disclaimer: 鈥淭his product is not affiliated with Jack Daniel Distillery.鈥 In the middle are some warnings and guarantees. And at the top, most relevant here, are two product logos鈥攐n the left for the Silly Squeakers line, and on the right for the Bad Spaniels toy.

Soon after Bad Spaniels hit the market, Jack Daniel鈥檚 sent VIP a letter demanding that it stop selling the product. VIP responded by bringing this suit, seeking a declaratory judgment that Bad Spaniels neither infringed nor diluted Jack Daniel鈥檚 trademarks. The complaint alleged, among other things, that VIP is 鈥渢he owner of all rights in its 鈥楤ad Spaniels鈥 trademark and trade dress for its durable rubber squeaky novelty dog toy.鈥 App. 3; see supra, at 6. Jack Daniel鈥檚 counterclaimed under the Lanham Act for both trademark infringement and trademark dilution by tarnishment.

VIP moved for summary judgment on both claims. First, VIP argued that Jack Daniel鈥檚 infringement claim failed under a threshold test derived from the First Amendment to protect 鈥渆xpressive works鈥濃攍ike (VIP said) the Bad Spaniels toy. When those works are involved, VIP contended, the so-called Rogers test requires dismissal of an infringement claim at the outset unless the complainant can show one of two things: that the challenged use of a mark 鈥渉as no artistic relevance to the underlying work鈥 or that it 鈥渆xplicitly misleads as to the source or the content of the work.鈥 Rogers v. Grimaldi, 875 F.2d 994, 999 (CA2 1989) (Newman, J.). Because Jack Daniel鈥檚 could make neither showing, VIP argued, the likelihood-of-confusion issue became irrelevant. Second, VIP urged that Jack Daniel鈥檚 could not succeed on a dilution claim because Bad Spaniels was a 鈥減arody[ ]鈥 of Jack Daniel鈥檚, and therefore made 鈥渇air use鈥 of its famous marks. 搂1125(c)(3)(A)(ii).

The District Court rejected both contentions for a common reason: because VIP had used the cribbed Jack Daniel鈥檚 features as trademarks鈥攖hat is, to identify the source of its own products. In the court鈥檚 view, when 鈥渁nother鈥檚 trademark is used for source identification鈥濃攁s the court thought was true here鈥攖he threshold Rogers test does not apply. App. to Pet. for Cert. 89a. Instead, the suit must address the 鈥渟tandard鈥 infringement question: whether the use is 鈥渓ikely to cause consumer confusion.鈥 Ibid. And likewise, VIP could not invoke the dilution provision鈥檚 fair-use exclusion. Parodies fall within that exclusion, the court explained, only when the uses they make of famous marks do not serve as 鈥渁 designation of source for the [alleged diluter鈥檚] own goods.鈥 Id., at 104a (quoting 搂1125(c)(3)(A)).

The case thus proceeded to a bench trial, where Jack Daniel鈥檚 prevailed. The District Court found, based largely on survey evidence, that consumers were likely to be confused about the source of the Bad Spaniels toy. See 291 F. Supp. 3d 891, 906鈥911 (D Ariz. 2018). And the court thought that the toy, by creating 鈥渘egative associations鈥 with 鈥渃anine excrement,鈥 would cause Jack Daniel鈥檚 鈥渞eputational harm.鈥 Id., at 903, 905.

But the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit reversed, ruling that the District Court had gotten the pretrial legal issues wrong. In the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 view, the infringement claim was subject to the threshold Rogers test because Bad Spaniels is an 鈥渆xpressive work鈥: Although just a dog toy, and 鈥渟urely not the equivalent of the Mona Lisa,鈥 it 鈥渃ommunicates a humorous message.鈥 953 F.3d 1170, 1175 (2020) (internal quotation marks omitted). The Court of Appeals therefore returned the case to the District Court to decide whether Jack Daniel鈥檚 could satisfy either of Rogers鈥 two prongs. And the Ninth Circuit awarded judgment on the dilution claim to VIP. The court did not address the statutory exclusion for parody and other fair use, as the District Court had. Instead, the Court of Appeals held that the exclusion for 鈥渘oncommercial use鈥 shielded VIP from liability. 搂1125(c)(3)(C). The 鈥渦se of a mark may be 鈥榥oncommercial,鈥 鈥 the court reasoned, 鈥渆ven if used to sell a product.鈥 953 F. 3d, at 1176 (internal quotation marks omitted). And here it was so, the court found, because it 鈥減arodies鈥 and 鈥渃omments humorously鈥 on Jack Daniel鈥檚. Id., at 1175; see id., at 1176.

On remand, the District Court found that Jack Daniel鈥檚 could not satisfy either prong of Rogers, and so granted summary judgment to VIP on infringement. Jack Daniel鈥檚 appealed, and the Ninth Circuit summarily affirmed.

We then granted certiorari to consider the Court of Appeals鈥 rulings on both infringement and dilution. 598 U. S. ___ (2022).

II

Our first and more substantial question concerns Jack Daniel鈥檚 infringement claim: Should the company have had to satisfy the Rogers threshold test before the case could proceed to the Lanham Act鈥檚 likelihood-of-confusion inquiry?[] The parties address that issue in the broadest possible way, either attacking or defending Rogers in all its possible applications. Today, we choose a narrower path. Without deciding whether Rogers has merit in other contexts, we hold that it does not when an alleged infringer uses a trademark in the way the Lanham Act most cares about: as a designation of source for the infringer鈥檚 own goods. See 搂1127; supra, at 2鈥3. VIP used the marks derived from Jack Daniel鈥檚 in that way, so the infringement claim here rises or falls on likelihood of confusion. But that inquiry is not blind to the expressive aspect of the Bad Spaniels toy that the Ninth Circuit highlighted. Beyond source designation, VIP uses the marks at issue in an effort to 鈥減arody鈥 or 鈥渕ake fun鈥 of Jack Daniel鈥檚. Tr. of Oral Arg. 58, 66. And that kind of message matters in assessing confusion because consumers are not so likely to think that the maker of a mocked product is itself doing the mocking.

A

To see why the Rogers test does not apply here, first consider the case from which it emerged. The defendants there had produced and distributed a film by Federico Fellini titled 鈥淕inger and Fred鈥 about two fictional Italian cabaret dancers (Pippo and Amelia) who imitated Ginger Rogers and Fred Astaire. When the film was released in the United States, Ginger Rogers objected under the Lanham Act to the use of her name. The Second Circuit rejected the claim. It reasoned that the titles of 鈥渁rtistic works,鈥 like the works themselves, have an 鈥渆xpressive element鈥 implicating 鈥 First Amendment values.鈥 875 F. 2d, at 998. And at the same time, such names posed only a 鈥渟light risk鈥 of confusing consumers about either 鈥渢he source or the content of the work.鈥 Id., at 999鈥1000. So, the court concluded, a threshold filter was appropriate. When a title 鈥渨ith at least some artistic relevance鈥 was not 鈥渆xplicitly misleading as to source or content,鈥 the claim could not go forward. Ibid. But the court made clear that it was not announcing a general rule. In the typical case, the court thought, the name of a product was more likely to indicate its source, and to be taken by consumers in just that way. See id., at 1000.

Over the decades, the lower courts adopting Rogers have confined it to similar cases, in which a trademark is used not to designate a work鈥檚 source, but solely to perform some other expressive function. So, for example, when the toymaker Mattel sued a band over the song 鈥淏arbie Girl鈥濃攚ith lyrics including 鈥淟ife in plastic, it鈥檚 fantastic鈥 and 鈥淚鈥檓 a blond bimbo girl, in a fantasy world鈥濃攖he Ninth Circuit applied Rogers. Mattel, Inc. v. MCA Records, Inc., 296 F.3d 894, 901 (2002). That was because, the court reasoned, the band鈥檚 use of the Barbie name was 鈥渘ot [as] a source identifier鈥: The use did not 鈥渟peak[ ] to [the song鈥檚] origin.鈥 Id., at 900, 902; see id., at 902 (a consumer would no more think that the song was 鈥減roduced by Mattel鈥 than would, 鈥渦pon hearing Janis Joplin croon 鈥極h Lord, won鈥檛 you buy me a Mercedes Benz?,鈥 . . . suspect that she and the carmaker had entered into a joint venture鈥). Similarly, the Eleventh Circuit dismissed a suit under Rogers when a sports artist depicted the Crimson Tide鈥檚 trademarked football uniforms solely to 鈥渕emorialize鈥 a notable event in 鈥渇ootball history.鈥 University of Ala. Bd. of Trustees v. New Life Art, Inc., 683 F.3d 1266, 1279 (2012). And when Louis Vuitton sued because a character in the film The Hangover: Part II described his luggage as a 鈥淟ouis Vuitton鈥 (though pronouncing it Lewis), a district court dismissed the complaint under Rogers. See Louis Vuitton Mallatier S. A. v. Warner Bros. Entertainment Inc., 868 F. Supp. 2d 172 (SDNY 2012). All parties agreed that the film was not using the Louis Vuitton mark as its 鈥渙wn identifying trademark.鈥 Id., at 180 (internal quotation marks omitted). When that is so, the court reasoned, 鈥渃onfusion will usually be unlikely,鈥 and the 鈥渋nterest in free expression鈥 counsels in favor of avoiding the standard Lanham Act test. Ibid.

The same courts, though, routinely conduct likelihood-of-confusion analysis, without mentioning Rogers, when trademarks are used as trademarks鈥i.e., to designate source. See, e.g., JL Beverage Co., LLC v. Jim Beam Brands Co., 828 F.3d 1098, 1102鈥1103, 1106 (CA9 2016); PlayNation Play Systems, Inc. v. Velex Corp., 924 F.3d 1159, 1164鈥1165 (CA11 2019). And the Second Circuit鈥Rogers鈥 home court鈥攈as made especially clear that Rogers does not apply in that context. For example, that court held that an offshoot political group鈥檚 use of the trademark 鈥淯nited We Stand America鈥 got no Rogers help because the use was as a source identifier. See United We Stand Am., Inc. v. United We Stand, Am. New York, Inc., 128 F.3d 86, 93 (1997). True, that slogan had expressive content. But the defendant group, the court reasoned, was using it 鈥渁s a mark,鈥 to suggest the 鈥渟ame source identification鈥 as the original 鈥減olitical movement.鈥 Ibid. And similarly, the Second Circuit (indeed, the judge who authored Rogers) rejected a motorcycle mechanic鈥檚 view that his modified version of Harley Davidson鈥檚 bar-and-shield logo was an expressive parody entitled to Rogers鈥 protection. See Harley-Davidson, Inc. v. Grottanelli, 164 F.3d 806, 812鈥813 (1999). The court acknowledged that the mechanic鈥檚 adapted logo conveyed a 鈥渟omewhat humorous[ ]鈥 message. Id., at 813. But his use of the logo was a quintessential 鈥渢rademark use鈥: to brand his 鈥渞epair and parts business鈥濃攖hrough signage, a newsletter, and T-shirts鈥攚ith images 鈥渟imilar鈥 to Harley-Davidson鈥檚. Id., at 809, 812鈥813.

The point is that whatever you make of Rogers鈥攁nd again, we take no position on that issue鈥攊t has always been a cabined doctrine. If we put this case to the side, the Rogers test has applied only to cases involving 鈥渘on-trademark uses鈥濃攐r otherwise said, cases in which 鈥渢he defendant has used the mark鈥 at issue in a 鈥渘on-source-identifying way.鈥 S. Dogan & M. Lemley, Grounding Trademark Law Through Trademark Use, 92 Iowa L. Rev. 1669, 1684 (2007); see id., at 1683鈥1684, and n. 58. The test has not insulated from ordinary trademark scrutiny the use of trademarks as trademarks, 鈥渢o identify or brand [a defendant鈥檚] goods or services.鈥 Id., at 1683.

We offer as one last example of that limitation a case with a striking resemblance to this one. It too involved dog products, though perfumes rather than toys. Yes, the defendant sold 鈥渁 line of pet perfumes whose names parody elegant brands sold for human consumption.鈥 Tommy Hilfiger Licensing, Inc. v. Nature Labs, LLC, 221 F. Supp. 2d 410, 412 (SDNY 2002) (Mukasey, J.). The product at issue was named Timmy Holedigger鈥攚hich Tommy Hilfiger didn鈥檛 much like. The defendant asked for application of Rogers. The court declined it, relying on Harley-Davidson. See 221 F. Supp. 2d, at 414. Rogers, the court explained, kicks in when a suit involves solely 鈥渘ontrademark uses of [a] mark鈥攖hat is, where the trademark is not being used to indicate the source or origin鈥 of a product, but only to convey a different kind of message. 221 F. Supp. 2d, at 414. When, instead, the use is 鈥渁t least in part鈥 for 鈥渟ource identification鈥濃攚hen the defendant may be 鈥渢rading on the good will of the trademark owner to market its own goods鈥濃Rogers has no proper role. 221 F. Supp. 2d, at 414鈥415. And that is so, the court continued, even if the defendant is also 鈥渕aking an expressive comment,鈥 including a parody of a different product. Id., at 415. The defendant is still 鈥渕ak[ing] trademark use of another鈥檚 mark,鈥 and must meet an infringement claim on the usual battleground of 鈥渓ikelihood of confusion.鈥 Id., at 416.

That conclusion fits trademark law, and reflects its primary mission. From its definition of 鈥渢rademark鈥 onward, the Lanham Act views marks as source identifiers鈥攁s things that function to 鈥渋ndicate the source鈥 of goods, and so to 鈥渄istinguish鈥 them from ones 鈥渕anufactured or sold by others.鈥 搂1127; see supra, at 2鈥3. The cardinal sin under the law, as described earlier, is to undermine that function. See supra, at 3. It is to confuse consumers about source鈥攖o make (some of ) them think that one producer鈥檚 products are another鈥檚. And that kind of confusion is most likely to arise when someone uses another鈥檚 trademark as a trademark鈥攎eaning, again, as a source identifier鈥攔ather than for some other expressive function. To adapt one of the cases noted above: Suppose a filmmaker uses a Louis Vuitton suitcase to convey something about a character (he is the kind of person who wants to be seen with the product but doesn鈥檛 know how to pronounce its name). See supra, at 12. Now think about a different scenario: A luggage manufacturer uses an ever-so-slightly modified LV logo to make inroads in the suitcase market. The greater likelihood of confusion inheres in the latter use, because it is the one conveying information (or misinformation) about who is responsible for a product. That kind of use 鈥渋mplicate[s] the core concerns of trademark law鈥 and creates 鈥渢he paradigmatic infringement case.鈥 G. Dinwoodie & M. Janis, Confusion Over Use: Contextualism in Trademark Law, 92 Iowa L. Rev. 1597, 1636 (2007). So the Rogers test鈥攚hich offers an escape from the likelihood-of-confusion inquiry and a shortcut to dismissal鈥攈as no proper application.

Nor does that result change because the use of a mark has other expressive content鈥i.e., because it conveys some message on top of source. Here is where we most dramatically part ways with the Ninth Circuit, which thought that because Bad Spaniels 鈥渃ommunicates a humorous message,鈥 it is automatically entitled to Rogers鈥 protection. 953 F. 3d, at 1175 (internal quotation marks omitted). On that view, Rogers might take over much of the world. For trademarks are often expressive, in any number of ways. Consider how one liqueur brand鈥檚 trade dress (beyond identifying source) tells a story, with a bottle in the shape of a friar鈥檚 habit connoting the product鈥檚 olden monastic roots:

Or take a band name that 鈥渘ot only identifies the band but expresses a view about social issues.鈥 Tam, 582 U. S., at 245 (opinion of Alito, J.) (discussing 鈥淭he Slants鈥). Or note how a mark can both function as a mark and have parodic content鈥攁s the court found in the Hilfiger/Holedigger litigation. See supra, at 13鈥14. The examples could go on and on. As a leading treatise puts the point, the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 expansion of Rogers 鈥減otentially encompasses just about everything鈥 because names, phrases, symbols, designs, and their varied combinations often 鈥渃ontain some 鈥榚xpressive鈥 message鈥 unrelated to source. 6 McCarthy 搂31:144.50. That message may well be relevant in assessing the likelihood of confusion between two marks, as we address below. See infra, at 18鈥19. But few cases would even get to the likelihood-of-confusion inquiry if all expressive content triggered the Rogers filter. In that event, the Rogers exception would become the general rule, in conflict with courts鈥 longstanding view of trademark law.

The Ninth Circuit was mistaken to believe that the First Amendment demanded such a result. The court thought that trademark law would otherwise 鈥渇ail[ ] to account for the full weight of the public鈥檚 interest in free expression.鈥 953 F. 3d, at 1174. But as the Mattel (i.e., Barbie) court noted, when a challenged trademark use functions as 鈥渟ource-identifying,鈥 trademark rights 鈥減lay well with the First Amendment鈥: 鈥淲hatever first amendment rights you may have in calling the brew you make in your bathtub 鈥楶epsi鈥 鈥 are 鈥渙utweighed by the buyer鈥檚 interest in not being fooled into buying it.鈥 296 F. 3d, at 900. Or in less colorful terms: 鈥淸T]o the extent a trademark is confusing鈥 as to a product鈥檚 source 鈥渢he law can protect consumers and trademark owners.鈥 Tam, 582 U. S., at 252 (Kennedy, J., concurring in part and concurring in judgment); see Friedman v. Rogers, 440 U.S. 1, 15 (1979) (rejecting a First Amendment challenge to a law restricting trade names because of the 鈥渟ubstantial鈥 interest in 鈥減rotecting the public from [their] deceptive and misleading use鈥). Or yet again, in an especially clear rendering: 鈥淸T]he trademark law generally prevails over the First Amendment鈥 when 鈥渁nother鈥檚 trademark (or a confusingly similar mark) is used without permission鈥 as a means of 鈥渟ource identification.鈥 Yankee Publishing Inc. v. News Am. Publishing Inc., 809 F. Supp. 267, 276 (SDNY 1992) (Leval, J.) (emphasis deleted). So for those uses, the First Amendment does not demand a threshold inquiry like the Rogers test. When a mark is used as a mark (except, potentially, in rare situations), the likelihood-of-confusion inquiry does enough work to account for the interest in free expression.

B

Here, the District Court correctly held that 鈥淰IP uses its Bad Spaniels trademark and trade dress as source identifiers of its dog toy.鈥 See App. to Pet. for Cert. 105a. In fact, VIP conceded that point below. In its complaint, VIP alleged that it both 鈥渙wn[s] and 鈥渦se[s]鈥 the 鈥 鈥楤ad Spaniels鈥 trademark and trade dress for its durable rubber squeaky novelty dog toy.鈥 App. 3, 11. The company thus represented in this very suit that the mark and dress, although not registered, are used to 鈥渋dentify and distinguish [VIP鈥檚] goods鈥 and to 鈥渋ndicate [their] source.鈥 搂1127. (Registration of marks, you鈥檒l recall, is optional. See supra, at 3鈥4.)

In this Court, VIP says the complaint was a mere 鈥渇orm allegation鈥濃攁 matter of 鈥渞ote.鈥 Tr. of Oral Arg. 73. But even if we knew what that meant, VIP has said and done more in the same direction. First, there is the way the product is marketed. On the hangtag, the Bad Spaniels logo sits opposite the concededly trademarked Silly Squeakers logo, with both appearing to serve the same source-identifying function. See supra, at 7. And second, there is VIP鈥檚 practice as to other products in the Silly Squeakers line. The company has consistently argued in court that it owns, though has never registered, the trademark and trade dress in dog toys like 鈥淛ose Perro鈥 (cf. Jose Cuervo) and 鈥淗einieSniff 鈥檔鈥 (cf. Heineken).[] And it has chosen to register the names of still other dog toys, including Dos Perros (#6176781), Smella Arpaw (#6262975), and Doggie Walker (#6213816). See supra, at 6. Put all that together, and more than 鈥渇orm鈥 or 鈥渞ote鈥 emerges: VIP鈥檚 conduct is its own admission that it is using the Bad Spaniels (n茅e Jack Daniel鈥檚) trademarks as trademarks, to identify product source.

Because that is so, the only question in this suit going forward is whether the Bad Spaniels marks are likely to cause confusion. There is no threshold test working to kick out all cases involving 鈥渆xpressive works.鈥 But a trademark鈥檚 expressive message鈥攑articularly a parodic one, as VIP asserts鈥攎ay properly figure in assessing the likelihood of confusion. See, e.g., Louis Vuitton Malletier S. A. v. Haute Diggity Dog, LLC, 507 F.3d 252, 265 (CA4 2007) (Parody 鈥渋nfluences the way in which the [likelihood-of-confusion] factors are applied鈥); Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 17鈥22 (same). A parody must 鈥渃onjure up鈥 鈥渆nough of [an] original to make the object of its critical wit recognizable.鈥 Campbell v. Acuff-Rose Music, Inc., 510 U.S. 569, 588 (1994) (internal quotation marks omitted). Yet to succeed, the parody must also create contrasts, so that its message of ridicule or pointed humor comes clear. And once that is done (if that is done), a parody is not often likely to create confusion. Self-deprecation is one thing; self-mockery far less ordinary. So although VIP鈥檚 effort to ridicule Jack Daniel鈥檚 does not justify use of the Rogers test, it may make a difference in the standard trademark analysis. Consistent with our ordinary practice, we remand that issue to the courts below. See Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U.S. 709, 718, n. 7 (2005) (noting that this Court is generally 鈥渁 court of review, not of first view鈥).

III

Our second question, more easily dispatched, concerns Jack Daniel鈥檚 claim of dilution by tarnishment (for the linkage of its whiskey to less savory substances). Recall that the Ninth Circuit dismissed that claim based on one of the Lanham Act鈥檚 鈥淸e]xclusions鈥 from dilution liability鈥攆or 鈥淸a]ny noncommercial use of a mark.鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(C); see supra, at 9. On the court鈥檚 view, the 鈥渦se of a mark may be 鈥榥oncommercial鈥 even if used to sell a product.鈥 953 F. 3d, at 1176 (internal quotation marks omitted). And VIP鈥檚 use is so, the court continued, because it 鈥減arodies鈥 and 鈥渃onvey[s] a humorous message鈥 about Jack Daniel鈥檚. Id., at 1175鈥1176. We need not express a view on the first step of that reasoning because we think the second step wrong. However wide the scope of the 鈥渘oncommercial use鈥 exclusion, it cannot include, as the Ninth Circuit thought, every parody or humorous commentary.

To begin to see why, consider the scope of another of the Lanham Act鈥檚 exclusions鈥攖his one for 鈥淸a]ny fair use.鈥 As described earlier, the 鈥渇air use鈥 exclusion specifically covers uses 鈥減arodying, criticizing, or commenting upon鈥 a famous mark owner. 搂1125(c)(3)(A)(ii); see supra, at 5. But not in every circumstance. Critically, the fair-use exclusion has its own exclusion: It does not apply when the use is 鈥渁s a designation of source for the person鈥檚 own goods or services.鈥 搂1125(c)(3)(A). In that event, no parody, criticism, or commentary will rescue the alleged dilutor. It will be subject to liability regardless.

The problem with the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 approach is that it reverses that statutorily directed result, as this case illustrates. Given the fair-use provision鈥檚 carve-out, parody (and criticism and commentary, humorous or otherwise) is exempt from liability only if not used to designate source. Whereas on the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 view, parody (and so forth) is exempt always鈥攔egardless whether it designates source. The expansive view of the 鈥渘oncommercial use鈥 exclusion effectively nullifies Congress鈥檚 express limit on the fair-use exclusion for parody, etc. Just consider how the Ninth Circuit鈥檚 construction played out here. The District Court had rightly concluded that because VIP used the challenged marks as source identifiers, it could not benefit from the fair-use exclusion for parody. See App. to Pet. for Cert. 105a; supra, at 8鈥9, 17鈥18. The Ninth Circuit took no issue with that ruling. But it shielded VIP鈥檚 parodic uses anyway. In doing so, the court negated Congress鈥檚 judgment about when鈥攁nd when not鈥攑arody (and criticism and commentary) is excluded from dilution liability.

IV

Today鈥檚 opinion is narrow. We do not decide whether the Rogers test is ever appropriate, or how far the 鈥渘oncommercial use鈥 exclusion goes. On infringement, we hold only that Rogers does not apply when the challenged use of a mark is as a mark. On dilution, we hold only that the noncommercial exclusion does not shield parody or other commentary when its use of a mark is similarly source-identifying. It is no coincidence that both our holdings turn on whether the use of a mark is serving a source-designation function. The Lanham Act makes that fact crucial, in its effort to ensure that consumers can tell where goods come from.

For the reasons stated, we vacate the judgment below and remand for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.

It is so ordered.

Notes

[] To be clear, when we refer to 鈥渢he Rogers threshold test,鈥 we mean any threshold First Amendment filter.

[]  That is not to say (far from it) that every infringement case involving a source-identifying use requires full-scale litigation. Some of those uses will not present any plausible likelihood of confusion鈥攂ecause of dissimilarity in the marks or various contextual considerations. And if, in a given case, a plaintiff fails to plausibly allege a likelihood of confusion, the district court should dismiss the complaint under Federal Rule of Civil Procedure 12(b)(6). See 6 McCarthy 搂32:121.75 (providing examples).

[] See, e.g., VIP Products, LLC v. Tequila Cuervo La Rojena, S. A. de C. V., No. 20鈥揷v鈥0319 (D Ariz., Feb. 11, 2020), ECF Doc. 1, p. 3 (鈥淛ose Perro鈥); VIP Products, LLC v. Heineken USA, Inc., No. 13鈥揷v鈥0319 (D Ariz., Feb. 13, 2013), ECF Doc. 1, pp. 3鈥4 (鈥淗einieSniff 鈥檔鈥); VIP Products, LLC v. Pabst Brewing Co., No. 14鈥揷v鈥2084 (D Ariz., Sept. 19, 2014), ECF Doc. 1, pp. 3鈥4 (鈥淏lue Cats Trippin鈥) (cf. Pabst Blue Ribbon); VIP Products, LLC v. Champagne Louis Roederer, S. A., No. 13鈥揷v鈥2365 (D Ariz., Nov. 18, 2013), ECF Doc. 1, pp. 3鈥4 (鈥淐rispaw鈥) (cf. Cristal).


SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

No. 22鈥148

JACK DANIEL鈥橲 PROPERTIES, INC., PETITIONER v. VIP PRODUCTS LLC

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit

[June 8, 2023]

Justice Sotomayor, with whom Justice Alito joins, concurring.

I join the Court鈥檚 opinion in full. I write separately to emphasize that in the context of parodies and potentially other uses implicating First Amendment concerns, courts should treat the results of surveys with particular caution. As petitioner did here, plaintiffs in trademark infringement cases often commission surveys that purport to show that consumers are likely to be confused by an allegedly infringing product. Like any other evidence, surveys should be understood as merely one piece of the multifaceted likelihood of confusion analysis. See, e.g., Uncommon, LLC v. Spigen, Inc., 926 F.3d 409, 425 (CA7 2019). Courts should also carefully assess the methodology and representativeness of surveys, as many lower courts already do. See, e.g., Water Pik, Inc. v. Med-Systems, Inc., 726 F.3d 1136, 1144鈥1150 (CA10 2013); Starbucks Corp. v. Wolfe鈥檚 Borough Coffee, Inc., 588 F.3d 97, 117 (CA2 2009).

When an alleged trademark infringement involves a parody, however, there is particular risk in giving uncritical or undue weight to surveys. Survey answers may reflect a mistaken belief among some survey respondents that all parodies require permission from the owner of the parodied mark. Some of the answers to the survey in this case illustrate this potential. See App. 81鈥82, n. 25 (鈥 鈥業鈥檓 sure the dog toy company that made this toy had to get [Jack Daniel鈥檚] permission and legal rights to essentially copy the[ir] product in dog toy form鈥 鈥); ibid. (鈥 鈥楾he bottle is mimicked after the Jack Daniel BBQ sauce. So they would hold the patent therefore you would have to ask permission to use the image鈥 鈥); see also Anheuser-Busch, Inc. v. Balducci Publications, 28 F.3d 769, 772鈥773, 775 (CA8 1994) (describing a similar situation). Plaintiffs can point to this misunderstanding of the legal framework as evidence of consumer confusion. Cleverly designed surveys could also prompt such confusion by making consumers think about complex legal questions around permission that would not have arisen organically out in the world.

Allowing such survey results to drive the infringement analysis would risk silencing a great many parodies, even ones that by other metrics are unlikely to result in the confusion about sourcing that is the core concern of the Lanham Act. See ante, at 4, 10, 14. Well-heeled brands with the resources to commission surveys would be handed an effective veto over mockery. After all, 鈥淸n]o one likes to be the butt of a joke, not even a trademark.鈥 6 J. McCarthy, Trademarks and Unfair Competition 搂31:153 (5th ed. 2023). This would upset the Lanham Act鈥檚 careful balancing of 鈥渢he needs of merchants for identification as the provider of goods with the needs of society for free communication and discussion.鈥 P. Leval, Trademark: Champion of Free Speech, 27 Colum. J. L. & Arts 187, 210 (2004). Courts should thus ensure surveys do not completely displace other likelihood-of-confusion factors, which may more accurately track the experiences of actual consumers in the marketplace. Courts should also be attentive to ways in which surveys may artificially prompt such confusion about the law or fail to sufficiently control for it.


SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

No. 22鈥148

JACK DANIEL鈥橲 PROPERTIES, INC., PETITIONER v. VIP PRODUCTS LLC

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the ninth circuit

[June 8, 2023]

Justice Gorsuch, with whom Justice Thomas and Justice Barrett join, concurring.

I am pleased to join the Court鈥檚 opinion. I write separately only to underscore that lower courts should handle Rogers v. Grimaldi, 875 F.2d 994 (CA2 1989), with care. Today, the Court rightly concludes that, even taken on its own terms, Rogers does not apply to cases like the one before us. But in doing so, we necessarily leave much about Rogers unaddressed. For example, it is not entirely clear where the Rogers test comes from鈥攊s it commanded by the First Amendment, or is it merely gloss on the Lanham Act, perhaps inspired by constitutional-avoidance doctrine? Id., at 998. For another thing, it is not obvious that Rogers is correct in all its particulars鈥攃ertainly, the Solicitor General raises serious questions about the decision. See Brief for United States as Amicus Curiae 23鈥28. All this remains for resolution another day, ante, at 13, and lower courts should be attuned to that fact.

Share