果冻传媒app官方

Table of Contents

Speech Protected Under the First Amendment

Research & Learn

鈥淚f there is a bedrock principle underlying the First Amendment, it is that the government may not prohibit the expression of an idea simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or disagreeable.鈥 鈥 Texas v. Johnson (1989)

Young boy shouting on a megaphone in a protest

The First Amendment protects the government from censoring broad categories of speech. But what is speech?

The Supreme Court has consistently held the First Amendment to protect much more than 鈥渕ere鈥 words. As the Court noted in Cohen v. California (1971), the amendment protects not just speech but 鈥渃ommunication,鈥 even when it鈥檚 not in words. As a result, when you read 鈥渟peech鈥 in the First Amendment, you should 

Our courts have held that the First Amendment protects a dizzying array of communicative activities. Speech has been broadly defined as expression including, but not limited to, what you wear, read, say, paint, perform, believe, protest, or even silently resist. 鈥淪peech activities鈥 can include leafleting, picketing, symbolic acts, wearing armbands, demonstrations, speeches, forums, concerts, motion pictures, stage performances, remaining silent, and so on. 

Moreover, the subject of your 鈥渟peech鈥 is not confined to the realm of politics. The First Amendment protects purely emotional expression, religious expression, vulgarity, parody, and satire. Your speech need not be articulate or even rational, much less polite, to enjoy constitutional protection.

Is 鈥榟ate speech鈥 protected by the First Amendment?

Contrary to popular misconception, there is no First Amendment exception allowing the government to punish so-called hate speech.

Hateful speech may be punishable if it falls into another category of unprotected speech鈥揳nd the kind of 鈥渉ate speech鈥 people tend to have the greatest worries about frequently does fall into those categories. Hateful speech that incites imminent lawless action, is a true threat of serious bodily harm, or causes an immediate breach of the peace can be punished because it does those things, regardless of the reason, but not because it is hateful. 

The Supreme Court has held the First Amendment allows Americans to protest a soldier鈥檚 funeral with signs saying 鈥淕od Hates Fags鈥 and 鈥淭hank God for Dead Soldiers鈥 (Snyder v. Phelps), burn the American flag in protest (Texas v. Johnson and United States v. Eichman), give a racially charged speech to a restless crowd (Terminiello v. Chicago). Even cross-burnings in the manner of the Ku Klux Klan cannot be subjected to blanket bans (R.A.V. v. City of St. PaulVirginia v. Black). 

The most prominent case about flag-burning, Texas v. Johnson (1989), states the general rule the government must follow: 鈥済overnment may not prohibit the verbal or nonverbal expression of an idea merely because society finds the idea offensive or disagreeable.鈥 Federal courts have consistently followed this holding when applying the First Amendment.

While this means tolerating a great deal of speech that is widely considered offensive, a free society must give much breathing space to hateful speech in order to avoid thought control and the censorship of unpopular views by the government. Instead of stifling free speech, we, as free citizens, have the power to most effectively answer hateful speech through protest, mockery, debate, questioning, silence, or by simply walking away.

Learn more about the legality of hate speech

Harassment

While actual harassment is not protected by the First Amendment, simply labeling any kind of offensive speech as 鈥渉arassment鈥 does not make it punishable. There are many occasions on which courts have struck down anti-harassment regulations and laws because they were written in a way that would allow the authorities to punish a substantial amount of protected speech. 

To avoid this, courts have carefully crafted definitions of harassment so as to avoid conflicting with the First Amendment. In the educational context for example, the Supreme Court held in Davis v. Monroe County Board of Education (1999) that student-on-student harassment consists only of unwelcome, discriminatory conduct (which may include expression) that is 鈥渟o severe, pervasive, and objectively offensive, and that so undermines and detracts from the victims鈥 educational experience, that the victim-students are effectively denied equal access to an institution鈥檚 resources and opportunities.鈥

By definition, this includes only extreme and usually repetitive behavior 鈥 behavior so serious that it would prevent a reasonable person from receiving his or her education.

The government may also prohibit harassment, properly defined, in the workplace. This includes quid pro quo harassment 鈥 where a supervisor conditions continued employment or job benefits on sexual favors 鈥 and hostile work environment harassment based on race, sex, or another protected characteristic. The latter arises when the conduct is severe or pervasive enough to create a work environment that a reasonable person would consider hostile, abusive, or intimidating.

Charged political rhetoric

Political speech is 鈥渁t the core of what the First Amendment is designed to protect,鈥 and our system grants considerable deference to even threatening language posed in a political context, as the 鈥渓anguage of the political arena . . . is often vituperative, abusive, and inexact,鈥 according to the Supreme Court in Virginia v. Black (2003) and Watts v. United States (1969), respectively.

This is not a new development. Political discourse has long been steeped in themes of violence. Famously, Thomas Jefferson predicted that revolution and violence would be necessary to preserve liberty, writing: 鈥淭he tree of liberty must be refreshed from time to time with the blood of patriots and tyrants.鈥 And, of course, politics sometimes involves explicit calls for violence in the form of military action, from President Franklin D. Roosevelt鈥檚  requesting a declaration of war against Japan in 1941, to President George W. Bush鈥檚 : 鈥淢ake no mistake: The United States will hunt down and punish those responsible for these cowardly acts.鈥 The millions of Americans echoing those calls in the wake of the attack on Pearl Harbor and the terrorist attacks of 9/11 could not be punished for doing so.

Today, our national political conversation continues to be filled with impassioned speech on polarizing, high-stakes issues. This rhetoric is protected even if it is tinged with violent themes. While the First Amendment does not protect rhetoric that amounts to 鈥渢rue threats鈥 or 鈥渋ncitement,鈥 these are and must be narrow, precise exceptions. Expansive interpretations of these exceptions would chill the right to political expression, which embraces 鈥渢he right to criticize public men and measures 鈥 and that means not only informed and responsible criticism, but the freedom to speak foolishly and without moderation,鈥 according to the Supreme Court in  (1944).

Learn more about why (most) calls for genocide are protected speech

Why even (most) lies are protected speech

Few would consider lies beneficial to public discourse or human relationships. Even so, there are good reasons why our Constitution protects most forms of dishonesty, deception, and artful deviations from the truth.

It starts with this question: What exactly is a lie, anyway?

Most of us can agree that lies are the opposite of truth, but opinions vary from that point forward. Must lies require a conscious attempt to deceive? If the speaker honestly believes the falsehood is true, or carelessly repeats whatever they heard, is that lying? Can statements once thought to be true retroactively become lies once they鈥檙e discovered to be false?

Things get weirder when you start factoring in things like fiction, satire, or parody. Are those actually, or even technically, 鈥渓ies鈥? What if something is mostly true, or mostly false? At what point does a statement cross the threshold into being an official lie?

Collage young woman face head body fragment with hands covering mouth censorship

Unprotected Speech Synopsis

Issue Pages

果冻传媒app官方's guide to speech not protected by the First Amendment for educators and students outlining incitement, threats, defamation, and hate speech

Read More

And all of that assumes you can easily tell if someone is making a statement of fact versus one of opinion. If a person says 鈥渁ll politicians are crooks,鈥 are they lying if you can find one who isn鈥檛 a criminal, making the statement literally untrue? Or was their statement actually one of opinion?

Hopefully these questions illustrate the difficulty of knowing how and where to draw these lines. Now imagine trying to legislate all this. How can you legally tell the difference between lies and honest mistakes? How much does intention play into your definition, and how can you reasonably gauge it? Perhaps most importantly: How can you ensure that whatever laws you create to stamp out lies don鈥檛 get abused, or stamp out important truths along with them? 

This last question has been central to why discussions about regulating lies with laws have been so difficult, and why they鈥檝e almost always ended by erring on the side of letting false speech stay free.

The short answer to why lies are constitutionally protected is that, outside of properly defined defamation and fraud, as well as the few narrow and formally recognized categories of unprotected speech, the First Amendment is neutral regarding the content of the speech it defends.

This principle was expressed beautifully by Justice Thurgood Marshall in the 1972 Supreme Court case Police Department of Chicago v. Mosley, which questioned the constitutionality of a city ordinance banning non-union picketing outside of a school building. In the majority opinion, Marshall wrote, 鈥渢he First Amendment means that government has no power to restrict expression because of its message, its ideas, its subject matter, or its content.鈥

Learn more about why (most) lies are protected speech

Share