Table of Contents
The Case for Hate Speech
Disappointingly, when discussing free speech and its value to society, I have become accustomed to some variant of the inevitable rejoinder: 鈥淗ate speech is not free speech.鈥
This maxim has been repeated in discussions about everything from the protest against portrayal of the to the controversy surrounding the . It has been parroted by under the guise of constitutional truth. I have seen it painted without irony on the free speech wall of my own college.
Just as with free speech, there is a distinction to be drawn between hate speech in a legal context and hate speech as a more abstract concept. I would submit, however, that regardless of whether we are speaking legally or conceptually, 鈥渉ate speech鈥 can prove valuable to public understanding and must be protected.
In the United States, hate speech is not a recognized exception to the free speech protections under the First Amendment. Put simply, the vast majority of 鈥渉ate speech鈥 is free speech. In the 1969 Supreme Court decision Brandenburg v. Ohio, the justices assessed speech that would be considered 鈥渉ate鈥 by most people鈥檚 colloquial definitions: at issue was a Ku Klux Klan leader鈥檚 inflammatory speech urging listeners to take revenge on racial minorities. The court held that it did not constitute an incitement of lawlessness and was therefore constitutionally protected.
Similarly, in R.A.V. v. City of St. Paul, the court overturned a teenager鈥檚 conviction for burning a cross on a black family鈥檚 lawn. In R.A.V., the content of speech was determined to be an inadequate justification for prohibition. The right to the undoubtedly hateful speech of the Westboro Baptist Church was also upheld in Snyder v. Phelps, which dealt with the members鈥 protest ahead of a soldier鈥檚 funeral. The judgments in these cases establish a strong precedent against any sort of legislative attempt to punish hate speech in the United States.
To say that hate speech is not free speech in America is plainly false. The judiciary comprehends the imprudence of allowing a centralized authority to regulate not just what one is allowed to say, but what one is allowed to hear.
One of 果冻传媒app官方鈥檚 co-founders, Alan Charles Kors, about the importance of protecting hateful speech, recalls a A Man for All Seasons. In it, Thomas More states his refusal to arrest Richard Rich, a man who later conspires to have More convicted on false pretense, even 鈥淸i]f he were the Devil himself until he broke the law.鈥 Upon hearing this, Roper, More鈥檚 zealous son-in-law-to-be, asserts that he would cut down every law in England to get after the Devil. More responds:
And when the last law was down, and the Devil turned round on you where would you hide, Roper, the laws all being flat? 鈥 This country鈥檚 planted thick with laws from coast to coast 鈥 Man鈥檚 laws, not God鈥檚 鈥 and if you cut them down 鈥 and you鈥檙e just the man to do it 鈥 d鈥檡ou really think you could stand upright in the winds that would blow then? 鈥 Yes, I鈥檇 give the Devil benefit of law, for my own safety鈥檚 sake!
The question More poses evokes another: Who watches the watchmen?
If the law is thrown aside in order to prosecute some nebulous 鈥渂ad,鈥 what will happen to the 鈥済ood鈥 when the roles are reversed? If hate speech is to be defined, who gets to say what it is and is not?
This problem is not at all hypothetical. A recent example in Britain demonstrates how this can be abused. As a last ditch ploy to woo Muslim voters in the United Kingdom, Labour party candidate Ed Miliband of Islam a crime. And in France, following the Charlie Hebdo killings (which some seem to believe was a ), authorities arrested, among others, for a Facebook post expressing solidarity with Amedy Coulibaly, one of the shooters associated with the attack.
Thankfully, American legislatures cannot enact laws authorizing this sort of action. But as universities seek to suppress a broader range of speech they deem hateful, the power to control what students and faculty may discuss settles increasingly into the hands of campus administrators. This is of immediate concern to those who hold unpopular views. As Bolt鈥檚 Thomas More suggested, those who support administrators exercising discretion in this way might start to have their own viewpoints banned when the winds change.
Many will argue that speech can be both valuable and hateful, and many see offensive comedy and criticism of Islam as examples of that concept. But what about a more exclusive definition of hate speech limited to the most apparently unacceptable and frequently outlandish ideas? Is there any intrinsic value in Holocaust denial or advocacy of genocide?
In his book , FIREpresident Greg Lukianoff says, 鈥淚 believe the even greater failure of higher education is neglecting to teach the intellectual habits that promote debate and discussion, tolerance for views we hate, epistemic humility, and genuine pluralism.鈥
Why not ask ourselves how we know that the Holocaust occurred? Ideas are like muscles鈥攖hey atrophy if they are not properly exercised. Which is preferable: a person who accepts the Holocaust鈥檚 historicity based exclusively on the fact that it is what they have been told, or a person who experiences doubt and examines original documents, meets people with serial numbers tattooed on their arms, and visits the death camps or the mass graves? The fundamental point of epistemic humility is that it is not enough for a person to believe the truth; they should believe the truth for the right reasons. A quotation , and wise regardless of the original source, goes, 鈥淚t is the mark of an educated mind to be able to entertain a thought without accepting it.鈥
Some ideas are repugnant, and some people will hold these ideas against all reason. Even so, there is something to be learned from seeing a person express such an idea, if not from the idea itself. Ken Miller, an alumnus and professor at Brown University, penned an article he ever heard at the university. The leader of the American Nazi Party, himself a Brown alumnus, had come to speak. Miller learned firsthand the charisma with which pernicious ideas could be expressed. He understood the 鈥渁llure鈥 of fascism. Such an experience afforded students a visceral understanding both of history and of their own vulnerability. It was then perhaps the speaking, and not the speech, that was of lasting value.
If such lofty academic idealism fails to persuade, perhaps the simplest reason to permit such speech is that, as 果冻传媒app官方鈥檚 co-founder, Harvey Silverglate, put it: 鈥淚f there are Nazis in the room, I want to know who they are so that I can keep an eye on them.鈥
James Altschul is a FIREsummer intern.
Recent Articles
FIRE鈥檚 award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.