Table of Contents
First Amendment News 304: Cert. denial opinions of Thomas and Gorsuch in Berisha v. Lawson
Set out below are the dissents filed by Justices Clarence Thomas and Neil Gorsuch from the denial of certiorari in , this by way of a follow-up to FAN 302: "Cert. petition asks Justices to overrule 鈥榩ublic figure鈥 doctrine 鈥 relies heavily on 1993 Kagan book review" (June 23). Commentaries follow their opinions.
SHKELZEN BERISHA v. GUY LAWSON, ET AL.
ON PETITION FOR WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED
STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT No. 20鈥1063. Decided July 2, 2021
The petition for a writ of certiorari is denied.
JUSTICE THOMAS, dissenting from the denial of certiorari.
In 2015, Guy Lawson published a book detailing the 鈥渢rue story鈥 of how three Miami youngsters became international arms dealers. 973 F. 3d 1304, 1306 (CA11 2020). A central plot point involves the protagonists鈥 travels to Albania and subsequent run-ins with the 鈥淎lbanian mafia,鈥 a key figure of which, the book claims, is petitioner Shkelzen Berisha. The book performed well, and Lawson eventually sold the movie rights to Warner Bros., which made the feature film War Dogs.
Unhappy with his portrayal, Berisha sued Lawson for defamation under Florida law. According to Berisha, he is not associated with the Albanian mafia鈥攐r any dangerous group鈥攁nd Lawson recklessly relied on flimsy sources to contend that he was.
The District Court granted summary judgment in favor of Lawson. Setting aside questions of truth or falsity, the court simply asked whether Berisha is a 鈥減ublic figure.鈥 Why? Because under this Court鈥檚 First Amendment jurisprudence, public figures cannot establish libel without proving by clear and convincing evidence that the defendant acted with 鈥溾榓ctual malice鈥欌濃攖hat is with knowledge that the published material 鈥渨as false or with reckless dis- regard of whether it was false.鈥 New York Times Co. v. Sulivan, 376 U. S. 254, 280 (1964); accord, Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U. S. 323, 334鈥335, 342 (1974); Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U. S. 130, 155 (1967). After concluding that Berisha is a public figure (or at least is one for purposes of Albanian weapons-trafficking stories), the court found that he had not satisfied this high standard. The Eleventh Circuit affirmed.
Berisha now asks this Court to reconsider the 鈥渁ctual malice鈥 requirement as it applies to public figures. As I explained recently, we should. See McKee v. Cosby, 586 U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (opinion concurring in denial of certiorari) (slip op., at 2).
This Court鈥檚 pronouncement that the First Amendment requires public figures to establish actual malice bears 鈥渘o relation to the text, history, or structure of the Constitution.鈥 Tah v. Global Witness Publishing, Inc., 991 F. 3d 231, 251 (CADC 2021) (Silberman, J., dissenting) (emphasis deleted). In fact, the opposite rule historically prevailed: 鈥淸T]he common law deemed libels against public figures to be . . . more serious and injurious than ordinary libels.鈥 McKee, 586 U. S., at ___ (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (slip op., at 7).
The Court provided scant explanation for the decision to erect a new hurdle for public-figure plaintiffs so long after the First Amendment鈥檚 ratification. In Gertz, for example, the Court reasoned that public figures are fair targets because 鈥渢hey invite attention and comment.鈥 418 U. S., at 345. That is, 鈥減ublic officials and public figures have voluntarily exposed themselves to increased risk of injury from defamatory falsehood.鈥 Ibid. But it is unclear why exposing oneself to an increased risk of becoming a victim necessarily means forfeiting the remedies legislatures put in place for such victims. And, even assuming that it is sometimes fair to blame the victim, it is less clear why the rule still applies when the public figure 鈥渉as not voluntarily sought attention.鈥 378 F. Supp. 3d 1145, 1158 (SD Fla. 2018); see also Rosanova v. Playboy Enterprises, Inc., 580 F. 2d 859, 861 (CA5 1978) (鈥淚t is no answer to the assertion that one is a public figure to say, truthfully, that one doesn鈥檛 choose to be鈥).
The lack of historical support for this Court鈥檚 actual-mal- ice requirement is reason enough to take a second look at the Court鈥檚 doctrine. Our reconsideration is all the more needed because of the doctrine鈥檚 real-world effects. Public figure or private, lies impose real harm. Take, for instance, the shooting at a pizza shop rumored to be 鈥渢he home of a Satanic child sex abuse ring involving top Democrats such as Hillary Clinton,鈥 Kennedy, 鈥楶izzagate鈥 Gunman Sentenced to 4 Years in Prison, NPR (June 22, 2017), www.npr.org/section/the two-way/2017/06/22/533941689/pizzagate-gunman-sentenced-to-4-years-in-prison. Or consider how online posts falsely labeling someone as 鈥渁 thief, a fraudster, and a pedophile鈥 can spark the need to set up a home-security system. Hill, A Vast Web of Vengeance, N. Y. Times (Jan. 30, 2021), www.nytimes.com/2021/01/30/ technology/change-my-google-results.html. Or think of those who have had job opportunities withdrawn over false accusations of racism or anti-Semitism. See, e.g., Wemple, Bloomberg Law Tried To Suppress Its Erroneous Labor Dept. Story, Washington Post (Sept. 6, 2019), www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/2019/09/06/bloomberg-law- tried-suppress-its-erroneous-labor-dept-story. Or read about Kathrine McKee鈥攕urely this Court should not remove a woman鈥檚 right to defend her reputation in court simply because she accuses a powerful man of rape. See McKee, 586 U. S., at ___鈥揰__ (opinion of THOMAS, J.) (slip op., at 1鈥2).
The proliferation of falsehoods is, and always has been, a serious matter. Instead of continuing to insulate those who perpetrate lies from traditional remedies like libel suits, we should give them only the protection the First Amendment requires. I would grant certiorari.
JUSTICE GORSUCH, dissenting from the denial of certiorari.
The Bill of Rights protects the freedom of the press not as a favor to a particular industry, but because democracy cannot function without the free exchange of ideas. To govern themselves wisely, the framers knew, people must be able to speak and write, question old assumptions, and offer new insights. 鈥淚f a nation expects to be ignorant and free . . . it expects what never was and never will be. . . . There is no safe deposit for [liberty] but with the people . . . [w]here the press is free, and every man able to read.鈥 Letter from T. Jefferson to C. Yancey (Jan. 6, 1816), in 10 The Writings of Thomas Jefferson 4 (P. Ford ed. 1899).
Like most rights, this one comes with corresponding duties. The right to due process in court entails the duty to abide by the results that process produces. The right to speak freely includes the duty to allow others to have their say. From the outset, the right to publish was no different. At the founding, the freedom of the press generally meant the government could not impose prior restraints preventing individuals from publishing what they wished. But none of that meant publishers could defame people, ruining careers or lives, without consequence. Rather, those exercising the freedom of the press had a responsibility to try to get the facts right鈥攐r, like anyone else, answer in tort for the injuries they caused.
This principle extended far back in the common law and far forward into our Nation鈥檚 history. As Blackstone put it, 鈥淸e]very freeman has an undoubted right to lay what sentiments he pleases before the public,鈥 but if he publishes falsehoods 鈥渉e must take the consequence of his own temerity.鈥 4 W. Blackstone, Commentaries on the Laws of Eng- land 151鈥152 (1769). Or as Justice Story later explained, 鈥渢he liberty of the press do[es] not authorize malicious and injurious defamation.鈥 Dexter v. Spear, 7 F. Cas. 624 (No. 3,867) (CC RI 1825).
This was 鈥淸t]he accepted view鈥 in this Nation for more than two centuries. Herbert v. Lando, 441 U. S. 153, 158鈥 159, and n. 4 (1979). Accordingly, 鈥渇rom the very founding鈥 the law of defamation was 鈥渁lmost exclusively the business of state courts and legislatures.鈥 Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U. S. 323, 369鈥370 (1974) (White, J., dissenting). As a rule, that meant all persons could recover damages for injuries caused by false publications about them. See Kurland, The Original Understanding of the Freedom of the Press Provision of the First Amendment, 55 Miss. L. J. 225, 234鈥237 (1985); J. Baker, An Introduction to English Legal History 474鈥475 (5th ed. 2019); Epstein, Was New York Times v. Sullivan Wrong? 53 U. Chi. L. Rev. 782, 801鈥802 (1986); Peck v. Tribune Co., 214 U. S. 185, 189 (1909).
This changed only in 1964. In New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), this Court declared that public officials could no longer recover for defamation as everyone had for centuries. Now, public officials could pre- vail only by showing that an injurious falsehood was published with 鈥溾榓ctual malice.鈥欌 Id.,at279鈥280. Three years later, the Court extended its actual malice standard from 鈥減ublic officials鈥 in government to 鈥減ublic figures鈥 outside government. See generally Curtis Publishing Co. v. Butts, 388 U. S. 130 (1967). Later still, the Court cast the net even wider, applying its new standard to those who have achieved 鈥減ervasive fame or notoriety鈥 and those 鈥渓imited鈥 public figures who 鈥渧oluntarily injec[t]鈥 themselves or are 鈥渄rawn into a particular public controversy.鈥 Gertz, 418. The Court viewed these innovations 鈥渙verturning 200 years of libel law鈥 as 鈥渘ecessary to implement the First Amendment interest in 鈥榰ninhibited, robust, and wide-open debate on public issues.鈥 Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U. S. 749, 766 (1985) (White, J., concurring in judgment).
Since 1964, however, our Nation鈥檚 media landscape has shifted in ways few could have foreseen. Back then, building printing presses and amassing newspaper distribution networks demanded significant investment and expertise. See Logan, Rescuing Our Democracy by Rethinking New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 81 Ohio St. L. J. 759, 794 (2020) (Logan). Broadcasting required licenses for limited airwaves and access to highly specialized equipment. See ibid. Comparatively large companies dominated the press, often employing legions of investigative reporters, editors, and fact-checkers. See id., at 794鈥795. But 鈥淸t]he liberty of the press鈥 has never been 鈥渃onfined to newspapers and periodicals鈥; it has always 鈥渃omprehend[ed] every sort of publication which affords a vehicle of information and opinion.鈥 Lovell v. City of Griffin, 303 U. S. 444, 452 (1938); see also Sentelle, Freedom of the Press: A Liberty for All or a Privilege for a Few? 2013 Cato S. Ct. Rev. 15, 30鈥34. And thanks to revolutions in technology, today virtually anyone in this country can publish virtually anything for immediate consumption virtually anywhere in the world. Logan 803 (noting there are 4 billion active social media users worldwide).
The effect of these technological changes on our Nation鈥檚 media may be hard to overstate. Large numbers of newspapers and periodicals have failed. See Greico, Pew Research Center, Fast Facts About the Newspaper Indus- try鈥檚 Financial Struggles as McClatchy Files for Bankruptcy (Feb. 14, 2020), http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2020/02/14/fast-facts-about-the-newspaper-industrys-financial-struggles/. Network news has lost most of its viewers. Pew Research Center, Network Evening News Ratings (Mar. 13, 2006), https://www.journalism.org/ numbers/network-evening-news-ratings/. With their fall has come the rise of 24-hour cable news and online media platforms that 鈥渕onetize anything that garners clicks.鈥 Logan 800. No doubt, this new media world has many virtues鈥攏ot least the access it affords those who seek information about and the opportunity to debate public affairs. At the same time, some reports suggest that our new media environment also facilitates the spread of disinformation. Id., at 804. A study of one social network reportedly found that 鈥渇alsehood and rumor dominated truth by every metric, reaching more people, penetrating deeper . . . and doing so more quickly than accurate statements.鈥 Id., at 804, n. 302; see Vosoughi, Roy, & Aral, The Spread of True and False News Online, Science Magazine, Mar. 9, 2018, pp. 1146鈥 1151. All of which means that 鈥渢he distribution of disinformation鈥濃攚hich 鈥渃osts almost nothing to generate鈥濃攈as become a 鈥減rofitable鈥 business while 鈥渢he economic model that supported reporters, fact-checking, and editorial oversight鈥 has 鈥渄eeply erod[ed].鈥 Logan 800.
It鈥檚 hard not to wonder what these changes mean for the law. In 1964, the Court may have seen the actual malice standard as necessary 鈥渢o ensure that dissenting or critical voices are not crowded out of public debate.鈥 Brief in Opposition 22. But if that justification had force in a world with comparatively few platforms for speech, it鈥檚 less obvious what force it has in a world in which everyone carries a soapbox in their hands. Surely, too, the Court in 1964 may have thought the actual malice standard justified in part because other safeguards existed to deter the dissemination of defamatory falsehoods and misinformation. Logan 794鈥795. In that era, many major media outlets employed fact-checkers and editors, id., at 795, and one could argue that most strived to report true stories because, as 鈥渢he public gain[ed] greater confidence that what they read [wa]s true,鈥 they would be willing to 鈥減ay more for the information so provided,鈥 Epstein, 53 U. Chi. L. Rev., at 812. Less clear is what sway these justifications hold in a new era where the old economic model that supported reporters, fact-checking, and editorial oversight is disappearing.
These questions lead to other even more fundamental ones. When the Court originally adopted the actual malice standard, it took the view that tolerating the publication of some false information was a necessary and acceptable cost to pay to ensure truthful statements vital to democratic self-government were not inadvertently suppressed. See Sullivan, 376 U. S., at 270鈥272. But over time the actual malice standard has evolved from a high bar to recovery into an effective immunity from liability. Statistics show that the number of defamation trials involving publications has declined dramatically over the past few decades: In the 1980s there were on average 27 per year; in 2018 there were 3. Logan 808鈥810 (surveying data from the Media Law Resource Center). For those rare plaintiffs able to secure a favorable jury verdict, nearly one out of five today will have their awards eliminated in post-trial motions practice. Id., at 809. And any verdict that manages to make it past all that is still likely to be reversed on appeal. Perhaps in part because this Court鈥檚 jurisprudence has been understood to invite appellate courts to engage in the unusual practice of revisiting a jury鈥檚 factual determinations de novo, it appears just 1 of every 10 jury awards now survives appeal. Id., at 809鈥810.
The bottom line? It seems that publishing without investigation, fact-checking, or editing has become the optimal legal strategy. See id., at 778鈥779. Under the actual malice regime as it has evolved, 鈥渋gnorance is bliss.鈥 Id., at 778. Combine this legal incentive with the business incentives fostered by our new media world and the deck seems stacked against those with traditional (and expensive) journalistic standards鈥攁nd in favor of those who can disseminate the most sensational information as efficiently as possible without any particular concern for truth. See ibid. What started in 1964 with a decision to tolerate the occasional falsehood to ensure robust reporting by a comparative handful of print and broadcast outlets has evolved into an ironclad subsidy for the publication of falsehoods by means and on a scale previously unimaginable. Id., at 804. As Sullivan鈥檚 actual malice standard has come to apply in our new world, it鈥檚 hard not to ask whether it now even 鈥渃ut[s] against the very values underlying the decision.鈥 Kagan, A Libel Story: Sullivan Then and Now, 18 L. & Soc. Inquiry 197, 207 (1993) (reviewing A. Lewis, Make No Law: The Sullivan Case and the First Amendment (1991)). If ensuring an informed democratic debate is the goal, how well do we serve that interest with rules that no longer merely tolerate but encourage falsehoods in quantities no one could have envisioned almost 60 years ago?
Other developments raise still more questions. In 1964, the Court may have thought the actual malice standard would apply only to a small number of prominent government officials whose names were always in the news and whose actions involved the administration of public affairs. Here again, the Court may have thought that allowing some falsehoods about these persons and topics was an acceptable price to pay to ensure truthful statements vital to democratic self-government were not inadvertently sup-pressed. Perhaps the Court weighed the costs and benefits similarly when it extended the actual malice standard to the 鈥減ervasively famous鈥 and 鈥渓imited-purpose public figures.鈥
But today鈥檚 world casts a new light on these judgments as well. Now, private citizens can become 鈥減ublic figures鈥 on social media overnight. Individuals can be deemed 鈥渇amous鈥 because of their notoriety in certain channels of our now-highly segmented media even as they remain unknown in most. See, e.g., Hibdon v. Grabowski, 195 S. W. 3d 48, 59, 62 (Tenn. App. 2005) (holding that an individual was a limited-purpose public figure in part because he 鈥渆ntered into the jet ski business and voluntarily advertised on the newsgroup rec.sport.jetski, an Internet site that is accessible worldwide鈥). Lower courts have even said that an individual can become a limited purpose public figure simply by defending himself from a defamatory statement. See Berisha v. Lawson, 973 F. 3d 1304, 1311 (CA11 2020). Other persons, such as victims of sexual assault seeking to confront their assailants, might choose to enter the public square only reluctantly and yet wind up treated as limited-purpose public figures too. See McKee v. Cosby, 586 U. S. ___, ___ (2019) (THOMAS, J., concurring in denial of certiorari) (slip op., at 1). In many ways, it seems we have arrived in a world that dissenters proposed but majorities rejected in the Sullivan line of cases鈥攐ne in which, 鈥渧oluntarily or not, we are all public [figures] to some degree.鈥 Gertz, 418 U. S., at 364 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (brackets and internal quotation marks omitted).
Again, it鈥檚 unclear how well these modern developments serve Sullivan鈥檚 original purposes. Not only has the doctrine evolved into a subsidy for published falsehoods on a scale no one could have foreseen, it has come to leave far more people without redress than anyone could have predicted. And the very categories and tests this Court in- vented and instructed lower courts to use in this area鈥斺減ervasively famous,鈥 鈥渓imited-purpose public figure鈥濃攕eem increasingly malleable and even archaic when almost anyone can attract some degree of public notoriety in some media segment. Rules intended to ensure a robust debate over actions taken by high public officials carrying out the public鈥檚 business increasingly seem to leave even ordinary Americans without recourse for grievous defamation. At least as they are applied today, it鈥檚 far from obvious whether Sullivan鈥檚 rules do more to encourage people of goodwill to engage in democratic self-governance or discourage them from risking even the slightest step toward public life.
鈥淚n a country like ours, where the people . . . govern themselves through their elected representatives, adequate information about their government is of transcendent importance.鈥 Dun & Bradstreet, 472 U. S., at 767 (White, J., concurring in judgment). Without doubt, Sullivan sought to promote that goal as the Court saw the world in 1964. Departures from the Constitution鈥檚 original public meaning are usually the product of good intentions. But less clear is how well Sullivan and all its various extensions serve its intended goals in today鈥檚 changed world. Many Members of this Court have raised questions about various aspects of Sullivan. See, e.g., McKee, 586 U. S., at ___ (opinion of THOMAS, J.); Coughlin v. Westinghouse Broadcasting & Cable, Inc., 476 U. S. 1187 (1986) (Burger, C. J., joined by Rehnquist, J., dissenting from denial of certiorari); Gertz, 418 U. S., at 370 (White, J., dissenting); Rosenbloom v. Metromedia, Inc., 403 U. S. 29, 62 (1971) (Harlan, J., dissenting); id., at 78 (Marshall, J., dissenting); Rosenblatt v. Baer, 383 U. S. 75, 92鈥93 (1966) (Stewart, J., concurring); see also Kagan, 18 L. & Soc. Inquiry, at 205, 209; Lewis & Ottley, New York Times v. Sullivan at 50, 64 De Paul L. Rev. 1, 35鈥36 (2014) (collecting statements from Justice Scalia). JUSTICE THOMAS does so again today. In adding my voice to theirs, I do not profess any sure answers. I am not even certain of all the questions we should be asking. But given the momentous changes in the Nation鈥檚 media landscape since 1964, I cannot help but think the Court would profit from returning its attention, whether in this case or another, to a field so vital to the 鈥渟afe deposit鈥 of our liberties.
Related
- Eugene Volokh, "," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 2)
- Eugene Volokh, "," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 2)
- Jonathan Alder, "," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 2)
Commentaries on California tax-exempt disclosure case
- Eugene Volokh, "," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 1)
- Josh Blackman, "," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 1)
- Steven D. Schwinn, "," Constitutional Law Prof Blog (July 2)
- "," Gibson Dunn (July 1)
Commentary from Ross on Mahanoy Area School District v. B.L.
- Catherine Ross, "," First Amendment Watch (July 6)
The Supreme Court鈥檚 failure to define off-campus speech and to provide guidance to school administrators and lower courts about whether, when, and on what grounds schools may regulate and punish students for what they say on their own time from their own equipment, is likely to lead to much additional litigation鈥攁nd to even more incidents in which schools punish off-campus expression that never reach a court. The ACLU, which so ably represented Levy, and similar public interest groups can expect to send a lot of lawyers鈥 letters to school districts and localities as the latter test exactly how wide a door Mahanoy opened.
The lack of practical guidance in Mahanoy should not come as a surprise. Concurring in Morse v. Frederick, Justice Breyer had urged the Court to rule in favor of the principal who censored the BONG HiTS 4 JESUS banner on the ground of qualified immunity: that is, a defense based on the claim that a public employee can not be held accountable for violating someone鈥檚 constitutional rights if the law was not sufficiently clear when she acted. In Morse, Breyer cautioned that the 鈥淐ourt need not and should not decide this difficult First Amendment issue on the merits.鈥 (20) Addressing concerns about abandoning the Supreme Court鈥檚 guidance function, Breyer doubted that the Court had offered 鈥減ractically valuable guidance鈥 in the case or that it could easily do so, because 鈥渟chool officials need a degree of Flexible authority.鈥Although qualified immunity was not at issue in Mahanoy, Breyer鈥檚 opinion for the Court largely avoided reaching the merits of 鈥渄ifficult First Amendment鈥 questions about the limits of school authority. The Court鈥檚 reluctance to craft any parameters leaves school officials named as defendants in future lawsuits in an excellent position to claim qualified immunity.
The lack of guidance, much less clarity, in Mahanoy will likely lead to the result Breyer feared would arise from the court鈥檚 generalities in Morse: 鈥渇urther disputes among teachers and students鈥 that will likely 鈥渕ake their way from the schoolhouse to the courthouse.鈥 Under Mahanoy those disputes will have an extra step: they will make their way from the student鈥檚 home to the courthouse and through the schoolhouse.
Volokh on social media platforms
- Eugene Volokh, "," Journal of Free Speech Law (2021)
Rudenstine on the Pentagon Papers case & its meaning today
- David Rudenstine, "," First Amendment Watch (June 30)
Journal of Free Speech Law call for papers
- Eugene Volokh, ",鈥 The Volokh Conspiracy (July 1)
Americans for Prosperity v. Bonta just came down, and the Journal of Free Speech Law, a new peer-reviewed, faculty-edited journal, plans to quickly publish two to four articles on this case, as a symposium issue鈥攏ot case notes as such, but rather articles on the broader subject (the future of disclosure requirements, or freedom of association more broadly) in light of the new decision. And given our publication speed, these will likely be the first such articles to be published in a full-fledged law journal.
Our plan:
- We need to see submissions by Aug. 1 (or earlier), but given the short timeline, we'll be open for rougher submissions than usual. What we want to see, to make our decision, is a clear explanation of the key novel, interesting, and useful contributions that the article would make.
- We require exclusive submissions (via Scholastica, ), but we will give an answer within two weeks (our average response time so far is under a week) of Aug. 1. Thus, if we say no, there will be plenty of time to submit to other journals in the August submission cycle.
- We plan on publishing the articles online and on Westlaw as soon as the author provides a publishable version, which could be as quickly as early September (or longer, if the author so requires).
- Our journal also publishes in print. We expect the print edition to come out towards the end of the year, depending on the timeline for the articles; but we expect that these days the important thing is getting the article out quickly online.
- We will set up online symposia on the drafts, so that authors can get feedback from the other authors and from other First Amendment scholars.
2020-2021 SCOTUS term: Free expression & related cases
Cases decided
- (consolidated with )
- (OA: April 28, 2021) (Re: K-12 punishment for online speech) (Held: 8-1, school district decision to suspend cheerleader for vulgar social media post violates the First Amendment)
- (OA: Nov. 4, 2020) (Religious expression: Free exercise & free speech claims) (decided on free exercise grounds)
- (Per curium, 7-1 with Thomas, J., dissenting) (Judgment vacated and remanded to 5th Cir.)
- (OA: Dec. 8, 2020) (Telephone Consumer Protection Act robocall case 鈥 decided on statutory grounds)
Cases argued
- (OA: Oct. 5, 2020) (Standing/judicial elections)
- (OA: April 26, 2021)
Cert. granted
- (judgment vacated and case is remanded to the Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit for consideration in light of Americans for Prosperity Foundation v. Bonta)
- (Judgment is vacated, and the case is remanded to the Second Circuit to dismiss as moot)
Pending petitions
Cert. denied
- (Justice Thomas, dissenting from denial of cert. (Detached Opinion) Justice Gorsuch, dissenting from denial of cert.)
- (see Josh Blackman, "After Seven Years of Litigation, Justices Kavanaugh and Barrett Let Arlene's Flowers Wilt," The Volokh Conspiracy (July 2, 2021)
- (Institute for Free Speech in support of Petitioners)
First Amendment-related
- (Re: Scope of Noerr-Pennington doctrine) (cert. denied)
- (Cert. denied)
- (Nominal damages and mootness in campus speech context) (Cert. granted: 8-1 held Art. III claim not moot)
- (Re: Section 202(h) of the Telecommunications Act of 1996) (Cert. granted & case argued) (Held: 9-0: FCC decision to repeal or modify three of its media ownership rules was not arbitrary or capricious under the Administrative Procedure Act)
- (Re: FCC cross-ownership restrictions) (Cert. granted & case argued 鈥 held the FCC's decision to repeal or modify three of its media ownership rules was not arbitrary or capricious for purposes of the Administrative Procedure Act.)
- (State anti-SLAPP laws in federal diversity cases) (cert. denied)
Last FAN
Recent Articles
FIRE鈥檚 award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.