Table of Contents
FIREpushes for a posthumous pardon: A symbolic act with a real-world wake-up message 鈥 First Amendment News 428
So what鈥檚 the point of a ? I mean, it sure as hell isn鈥檛 going to help the dead. They already paid the wrongful dues. It may help the living win favor (or attempt to win favor), as in the case of President Donald Trump鈥檚 ironic of the feminist Susan B. Anthony, if only to curry favor with anti-abortionists who champion Anthony鈥檚 鈥減ro-life鈥 views. Sometimes such pardons are given to settle a factually contested set of circumstances: Did the rock singer Jim Morrison actually come on stage during a 1969 concert and expose himself? Thus in 2010, on the occasion of Morrison鈥檚 birthday, Florida Governor Charlie Crist for The Doors鈥 lead singer.
Sometimes posthumous pardons are granted to draw attention to egregious past violations of our free speech freedoms. Two notable examples of that are New York Gov. George Pataki鈥檚 2003 , who had been convicted of obscenity, and Montana Gov. Brian Schweitzer鈥檚 convicted of sedition amid the anti-German hysteria of the First World War.
And sometimes a posthumous pardon is sought to both draw attention to a past First Amendment wrong and to alert people to the ongoing perils of an old law with modern-day potential for abridging our freedoms, which brings me to FIRE鈥檚 petition to President Joe Biden to posthumously pardon (1818-1882).
A symbolic gesture with real-world implications
To help set up the historical context and the contemporary threats posed by an old law, consider the following statement released by 果冻传媒app官方:
In 1879, newspaper publisher D.M. Bennett was arrested, convicted, and sentenced to thirteen months of hard labor in Albany prison for violating the . His crime? Officially, it was for mailing a copy of an anti-marriage tract titled 鈥淐upid鈥檚 Yokes, or The Binding Forces of Conjugal Life,鈥 which Anthony Comstock considered obscene. In reality, Bennett was targeted because he actively campaigned for the repeal of the Comstock Act in the pages of The Truth Seeker, the freethought magazine he had founded, and for which Roderick Bradford currently serves as chief editor.
We cannot allow the use of Victorian-Era laws to undermine the rights of American citizens. That鈥檚 why the FIREfiled a petition on June 17 on behalf of freethought publisher Roderick Bradford, calling on President Joe Biden to posthumously pardon one of the Comstock Act鈥檚 prominent victims, D.M. Bennett.
Here are a few excerpts from the petition to the President:
Pursuant to Article II, Section 2, Cl. 1 of the United States Constitution and 28 CFR 搂 1.1, Roderick Bradford, publisher of The Truth Seeker, respectfully requests a posthumous pardon for DeRobigne Mortimer Bennett (鈥淒.M. Bennett鈥), the founder of The Truth Seeker, who was convicted in 1879 of violating the 鈥淎ct for the Suppression of Trade in and Circulation of Obscene Literature and Articles of Immoral Use,鈥 Act of March 3, 1873, ch. 258, 搂 2, 17 Stat. 599, commonly known as the Comstock Act.
The Comstock Act has been much in the news of late because of efforts to revive its long-moribund provisions in ongoing debates over freedom of expression, abortion, and contraceptives. Although framed as an obscenity law, the Act was so broadly worded that it was used to prosecute literature, art, scientific and medical texts, and, in Bennett鈥檚 case, the publisher of a freethought journal. It was also wielded as a weapon against opponents of the Comstock Act who, like D.M. Bennett, advocated for its repeal. Developments in constitutional law through the twentieth century rendered the statute largely a dead letter, but recent events are threatening to breathe new life into this obsolete law.
By granting this pardon, the President would help right the injustice resulting from D.M. Bennett鈥檚 wrongful prosecution and conviction, and at the same time send the important message that Victorian Era laws should not be revived to undermine Americans鈥 individual rights. As philosopher George Santayana warned, 鈥渢hose who cannot remember the past are condemned to repeat it.鈥 In this regard, a posthumous pardon for D.M. Bennett would be an act of remembrance that may help forestall reliving a lamentable past.
- See also Susanna Granieri, 鈥,鈥 First Amendment Watch (June 12)
Why is this petition important today?
To answer that question, let me draw from what is set out in the petition itself:
A pardon of D.M. Bennett would serve as a reminder of what happens when laws to enforce public morality override constitutional protections for freedom of expression. Bennett鈥檚 prosecution starkly illustrates what can go wrong when enforcement of the law becomes politicized to crush political opponents. Admittedly, a posthumous pardon, by definition, cannot alter the plight of the deceased. In that narrow sense, such a pardon comes too late to save a living person from the acknowledged wrongs committed by the government. But a posthumous pardon does have other important and socially beneficial effects:
- It corrects the institutional record by publicly expunging the guilt associated with the unlawful or unconstitutional actions of the government.
- It has precedential value as an official declaration that such unlawful or unconstitutional action will not be repeated in the future.
- It corrects the reputational memory of the deceased person by clearing his or her name in the historical record.
- It serves as a public apology 鈥 an admission by the government that it once exerted its powers in ways that cannot be reconciled with the supreme law of the land.
- And, finally, it benefits the pardoner by placing him on the right side of history in proclaiming and upholding essential First Amendment freedoms.
This petition is important because no battle to preserve our rights is ever truly won, as Bennett鈥檚 case so well illustrates. Even under the undeveloped constitutional protections of the late nineteenth century, Bennett鈥檚 prosecution was a miscarriage of justice, and the evolution of First Amendment and constitutional law through the twentieth century rendered prosecutions like Bennett鈥檚 entirely unthinkable now. A December 2022 opinion of the Office of Legal Counsel described the law in question as 鈥渢he handiwork of Anthony Comstock 鈥 鈥榓 prominent anti-vice crusader who believed anything remotely touching upon sex was . . . obscene鈥 鈥 who successfully lobbied Congress and state legislatures in the nineteenth century to enact expansive laws 鈥榯o prevent the mails from being used to corrupt the public morals.鈥欌 Office of Legal Counsel Opinion, Application of the Comstock Act to the Mailing of Prescription Drugs That Can Be Used for Abortions, 46 Op. O.L.C. __ , slip op. at 3 (Dec. 23, 2022) (quoting Bolger v. Youngs Drug Prods. Corp., 463 U.S. 60, 70 n.19 (1983)). The OLC opinion observed the Comstock Act 鈥渋s perhaps best known for having prohibited the distribution of a wide range of writings until courts and the Executive Branch determined that the Free Speech Clause of the First Amendment significantly limited the permissible reach of the law.鈥 Id.
The lawyer behind the petition
Given the importance of correcting a historical wrong and the need to draw attention to the modern dangers posed by the Comstock Act, FIREenlisted the perfect person to draft the petition: First Amendment lawyer and author Robert Corn-Revere, the same lawyer I enlisted 20 some years to present a petition to posthumously pardon the uninhibited comedian Lenny Bruce.
Corn-Revere joined FIREfrom the law firm of Davis Wright Tremaine where he was a partner for 20 years specializing in freedom of expression and communications law. Before his time at DWT, he was a partner at Hogan & Hartson and served as legal advisor and later chief counsel to Federal Communications Commission Chairman James H. Quello.
In 2021, Cambridge University Press published his book, 鈥,鈥 which explores how free expression became a part of America鈥檚 identity. He also co-authored the three-volume treatise, 鈥溾 published by West Group.
Related
- 颁辞谤苍-搁别惫别谤别鈥檚&苍产蝉辫; to posthumously pardon Lenny Bruce
Justices unanimous in First Amendment trademark case 鈥 but differ on reasoning
- Ronald Mann, 鈥,鈥 SCOTUSblog (June 13)
The court on Thursday unanimously rejected an attempt to force the Patent and Trademark Office to accept the registration 鈥淭rump too small鈥 as a trademark for T-shirts mocking the former president. Steve Elster had argued that the provision of the Lanham Act that directs the PTO to refuse to register any mark that identifies 鈥渁 particular living individual鈥 violated his First Amendment rights. Although the justices splintered sharply on their reasoning, all agreed that the First Amendment permits the PTO to refuse to register the mark.
All nine justices agreed on the basic framework of analysis, which appears early in the principal opinion, written by Justice Clarence Thomas. Writing in that part of his opinion for six justices (all but Justices Elena Kagan, Sonia Sotomayor, and Ketanji Brown Jackson), Thomas explained that the restriction is viewpoint-neutral but not content-neutral. As he observed, the justices 鈥渉ave twice concluded that trademark restrictions that discriminate based on viewpoint violate the First Amendment.鈥 The earlier restrictions were viewpoint based because they 鈥減rohibited trademarks based only on one viewpoint, while permitting trademarks based on other viewpoints.鈥 The ban here, by contrast, is viewpoint neutral 鈥 Thomas pointed to the PTO鈥檚 refusal of trademarks such as 鈥淲elcome President Biden,鈥 鈥淚 Stump for Trump,鈥 and 鈥淥bama Pajama鈥 鈥 rejections that doubtless disappointed a broad range of political viewpoints. Having said that, Thomas explained that the restriction still is content-based, because it implements a ban based on the content of the trademark: 鈥淭he names clause turns on the content of the proposed trademark 鈥 whether it contains a person鈥檚 name. If the trademark does contain a person鈥檚 name, and the registrant lacks that person鈥檚 consent, then the names clause prohibits registration.鈥
The separate opinions show much less devotion to the historical approach. First, Justice Brett Kavanaugh and Chief Justice John Roberts joined most of Thomas鈥檚 opinion, but Kavanaugh wrote a brief concurrence explaining that the two of them were open to the possibility that 鈥渁 viewpoint-neutral, content-based trademark restriction might well be constitutional even absent such historical pedigree.鈥
Second, and more pointedly, Justice Amy Coney Barrett (joined in large part by Sotomayor, Kagan, and Jackson) wrote to explain her position that it was 鈥渨rong twice over鈥 to argue that 鈥渉istory and tradition鈥 alone can 鈥渟ettle the constitutionality of the names clause.鈥
Related
- 鈥,鈥 Gibson Dunn (June 13)
Today, the Supreme Court held that the Lanham Act鈥檚 prohibition on registration of trademarks that include a living person鈥檚 name without that person鈥檚 consent does not violate the First Amendment.
[ . . . ]
Although the Court鈥檚 judgment was unanimous, the fractured opinions demonstrate the Court鈥檚 disagreement about how to assess the constitutionality of content-based trademark registration requirements. The majority focused on history and tradition.
Justice Barrett in a separate opinion (joined by Justice Kagan in full and by Justices Sotomayor and Jackson in part) expressed the view that content-based restrictions should be upheld 鈥渟o long as they are reasonable in light of the trademark system鈥檚 purpose of facilitating source identification.鈥
Justice Sotomayor in a concurring opinion (joined by Justices Kagan and Jackson) said the Court should look to the 鈥渨ell-trodden terrain鈥 of 鈥渢rademark law and settled First Amendment precedent.鈥
Today鈥檚 ruling distinguished other recent Supreme Court decisions holding that restrictions on trademark registrations do violate the First Amendment when they discriminate based on viewpoint.
First Amendment Watch interview with BLM activist
- Susanna Granieri, 鈥,鈥 First Amendment Watch (June 4)
Black Lives Matter activist DeRay Mckesson has been involved in litigation for nearly eight years since a Louisiana police officer was reportedly struck in the head by a rock during a protest in Baton Rouge in July 2016. The officer sued Mckesson, claiming his involvement as an organizer in the protest made him liable.
The lawsuit against Mckesson, who told First Amendment Watch that he was not the organizer of the July 2016 protest, was filed in by the officer, who was initially known as John Doe in court records but has since been identified as Officer John Ford.
The protest, which began outside of the Baton Rouge Police Department on July 9, 2016, arose after the , a 37-year-old Black man, by a white police officer in Baton Rouge days earlier.
claimed that Black Lives Matter and Mckesson were responsible for his injury because Mckesson, according to the lawsuit, 鈥渋ncited the violence鈥 and 鈥渨as in charge of the protest.鈥
But a federal judge dismissed the lawsuit, stating that Black Lives Matter was not an entity that could be sued, and found that Mckesson 鈥渟olely engaged in protected speech鈥 during the protest. The U.S. Court of Appeals for the Fifth Circuit , and Mckesson which for review if Mckesson, under state law, could be sued.
The Fifth Circuit then that Mckesson鈥檚 involvement in organizing the protest meant that it鈥檚 鈥減lausible that Mckesson knew or should have known鈥 that a police response to the protest could lead to violence and injuries. It also rejected Mckesson鈥檚 claims that the First Amendment protects him from liability under state law.
Last month, another appeal from Mckesson in which that the court鈥檚 鈥渄enial today expresses no view about the merits of Mckesson鈥檚 claim.鈥
was whether a protest leader or organizer could be held liable for any illegal or violent actions committed by protest attendees, despite a leader鈥檚 possible lack of knowledge of such actions.
First Amendment Watch spoke with Mckesson about the legal dispute. He described the day of the protest, rejected claims that he was an organizer of the demonstration, and expressed concern over the impact of his case on the right to protest.
New scholarly article on fiction and defamation
- Collin O鈥橬eil, 鈥,鈥 Journal of Free Speech Law (June 10)
Speech damages someone's reputation when it leads others to believe that that person has done something that reflects poorly on their character. When that belief is also false the reputational damage is undeserved, and it is the point of American defamation law to protect individuals from suffering such undeserved reputational damage.
It is easy to understand why individuals would need protection from false and derogatory claims made about them in works of nonfiction, such as journalism, documentaries, and biographies. But it is not immediately clear why individuals would also need protection from fiction. Although authors of fiction often base their fictional characters on real people, they do not typically make real people characters in their stories. Even when they do put real people in their stories and depict them as doing bad things, the audience is still usually meant only to imagine the real people doing those bad things.
Nevertheless, some works of fiction are not only about real people but also do real and undeserved damage to their reputations. It may not be true, as has often been alleged, that Aristophanes's comedy The Clouds gave Socrates the reputation for rejecting the gods and corrupting the young that later led to his execution. But readers of parodies of news articles published on sites like The Onion and The Babylon Bee are sometimes duped, especially when they are already inclined to think poorly of the public figure that is being ridiculed.
Of course parodies are believed only when they are not recognized as parodies. But there are other genres of fiction that mix facts into the story, such as biofiction, biopics, and docudramas, and it is not always easy for audiences to distinguish what the author is making up from what the author is, or ought to be, trying to get right.
The biographical drama Amadeus suggested that Salieri poisoned Mozart, re-popularizing an old rumor about Salieri that the filmmakers must have at least strongly suspected was false. Salieri, being dead, is in no position to bring a lawsuit. But the villain of the docudrama When They See Us, Linda Fairstein, is alive and is suing Netflix and Ava DuVernay, the director, for defamation.
Fairstein was chief of Sex Crimes Prosecution during the investigation and prosecution of the "Central Park Five," five Black and Latino teenagers who were convicted of the beating and rape of a jogger in Central Park but who were exonerated years later after a serial rapist whose DNA was found at the scene confessed to the crime and said that he had acted alone. Fairstein alleges that she was defamed in several scenes in the docudrama, including in a scene where she is depicted as concealing potentially exculpatory evidence from the defense and a scene where she is depicted as instructing officers to use harsh interrogation techniques. As a result of her depiction in When They See Us, Fairstein's publishing contract was canceled (she had become a best-selling mystery writer since leaving the DA's office), her literary agents dropped her, #cancellindafairstein trended on Twitter, and Glamour magazine expressed regret they had named her Woman of the Year in 1993.
As the docudrama When They See Us makes clear, fiction about real people can do serious damage to their reputations. It is another question whether it is ever appropriate to hold an author of fiction legally liable for that damage. One aim of defamation law may be to reflect our pre-legal moral duties of care to avoid damaging others' reputations. If so, one important consideration for determining how defamation law should handle fiction is whether and when an author of fiction would count, morally speaking, as having wrongfully damaged someone's reputation.
But defamation law is also answerable to another moral value, namely, freedom of speech, that may be in tension with these pre-legal duties of care. Even when it is plausible that an author of fiction has wrongfully damaged someone's reputation, there might still be a reason of freedom of speech, even an overriding reason, to shield such an author from liability.
This Article will address the question of what limits, if any, freedom of speech would place on holding authors liable for the reputational damage they cause with fiction. By 鈥渇reedom of speech鈥 I will not be referring to the First Amendment but rather to one conception of the moral idea underlying it. According to this conception, the limits that freedom of speech places on the scope of authors' liability for causing false and defamatory beliefs are whatever limits are necessary to adequately protect our interests as potential authors and audiences, and whose costs are acceptable in terms of other interests. To apply this conception, it will be necessary to identify our interests as potential authors of and audiences for fiction about real people, and to assess how these interests would be affected by different limits.
Ultimately, I will argue that freedom of speech is consistent with holding authors liable for reputational damage caused by their violations of fiction鈥檚 鈥渧eracity rules鈥 and for reputational damage caused by mistakes that their target audience would be expected to make. But liability for beliefs that are traceable to mistakes that only an author鈥檚 incidental audience would be expected to make is, I will argue, prohibited by freedom of speech, so long as the costs of that protection remain acceptable.
More in the news
- Eugene Volokh, 鈥,鈥 The Volokh Conspiracy (June 17)
- 鈥,鈥 First Amendment Watch (June 17)
- Caity Coyne, 鈥,鈥 The 74 (June 17)
- Dan McCaleb, 鈥,鈥 The Center Square (June 16)
- Leyi Huang, 鈥,鈥 CBS 6 Albany (June 14)
2023-2024 SCOTUS term: Free expression and related cases
Cases Decided
- (certiorari granted, judgment re the bias policy claims vacated, and case remanded to the Court of Appeals for the 4th Circuit with instructions to dismiss those claims as moot) ()
Review granted
- (argued Nov. 1)
- (decided March 15, see below under 鈥淪tate action鈥)
- & (argued: Feb. 26)
- (argument: March 18)
- (argument: March 18)
- (argued March 20)
Pending petitions
State action
- (Barrett, J., 9-0: 鈥淭he state-action doctrine requires Lindke to show that Freed (1) had actual authority to speak on behalf of the State on a particular matter, and (2) purported to exercise that authority in the relevant posts. To the extent that this test differs from the one applied by the Sixth Circuit, we vacate its judgment and remand the case for further proceedings consistent with this opinion.鈥)
- (Per Curiam: 9-0: 鈥淲e granted certiorari in this case and in Lindke v. Freed (2024), to resolve a Circuit split about how to identify state action in the context of public officials using social media. Because the approach that the Ninth Circuit applied is different from the one we have elaborated in Lindke, we vacate the judgment below and remand the case to the Ninth Circuit for further proceedings consistent with our opinion in that case.鈥)
Review denied
- ( by Sotomayor, J.)
- (application for stay denied)
- (Justice Kavanaugh would grant the petition for a writ of certiorari. Justice Thomas, dissenting from the denial of certiorari. (separate ) Justice Alito, dissenting from the denial of certiorari. (separate )
Free speech related
- (pending) (statutory interpretation of 18 U.S.C. 搂&苍产蝉辫;1512(c) advocacy, lobbying and protest in connection with congressional proceedings) // See also (argued April 16)
Last scheduled FAN
FAN 427: 鈥Comedy in the time of cancel culture鈥
This article is part of First Amendment News, an editorially independent publication edited by Ronald K. L. Collins and hosted by FIREas part of our mission to educate the public about First Amendment issues. The opinions expressed are those of the article鈥檚 author(s) and may not reflect the opinions of FIREor Mr. Collins.
Recent Articles
FIRE鈥檚 award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.