Table of Contents
Why civility should not trump free expression: Part 10 of answers to bad arguments against free speech from Nadine Strossen and Greg Lukianoff
In May 2021, I published a list of 鈥鈥 with our friends over at. The great Nadine Strossen 鈥 former president of the ACLU from 1991 to 2008, and one of the foremost experts on freedom of speech alive today 鈥 saw the series and offered to provide her own answers to some important misconceptions about freedom of speech. My answers, when applicable, appear below hers.
Earlier in the series:
- Part 1: Free speech does not equal violence
- Part 2: Free speech is for everyone
- Part 3: Hate speech laws backfire
- Part 4: Free speech is bigger than the First Amendment
- Part 5: You can shout 鈥榝ire鈥 in a burning theater
- Part 6: Is free speech outdated?
- Part 7: Does free speech assume words are harmless?
- Part 8: Is free speech just a conservative talking point?
- Part 9: Free speech fosters cultural diversity
- Part 10: Why 'civility' should not trump free expression
- Part 11: 鈥楴ew鈥 justifications for censorship are never really new
- Part 12: Free speech isn鈥檛 free with a carveout for blasphemy
- Part 13: Does free speech lead inevitably to truth?
- Part 14: Shouting down speakers is mob censorship
Assertion: Restrictions on free speech are OK if they are made in the name of civility.
Nadine: This claim was effectively addressed in the justly celebrated 鈥,鈥 which the University of Chicago adopted in 2014, and which has since been adopted by many diverse public and private higher education institutions all over the U.S. The pertinent language states:
Although the university greatly values civility, and although all members of the university community share in the responsibility for maintaining a climate of mutual respect, concerns about civility and mutual respect can never be used as a justification for closing off discussion of ideas, however offensive or disagreeable those ideas may be to some members of our community.
As this statement acknowledges, it is certainly appropriate for public institutions, such as universities, to encourage members of their communities to express themselves in a civil and respectful manner. This approach, though, incorporates two important limits, which should be underscored.
First, what the institution encourages is a particular manner of expressing ideas, which involves no limit at all on which ideas are expressed. All things being equal, if one can convey one鈥檚 viewpoint through words, tone, gestures, and facial expressions that signal civility and respect, one should be encouraged to do so, and should do so voluntarily.
If an individual chooses to convey a message in an uncivil manner, that choice must be respected and protected
However, if the particular viewpoint cannot be conveyed through words and other means that audience members are likely to regard as civil and respectful, the viewpoint should nonetheless be conveyed.
Second, while university and other public officials may urge members of their communities to voluntarily express their ideas in a civil manner, they may not enforce any civility requirement. Accordingly, if an individual deliberately chooses to convey a message in an uncivil 鈥 even disrespectful 鈥 manner, that individual choice must be respected and protected.
Indeed, the incivility and disrespect may very well constitute integral elements of the substantive message. Consider, for example, messages that protest certain official conduct. If a member of the community objects to police misconduct, she may well convey her disrespect for the conduct, and for the officers who engaged in it, through intentionally disrespectful language. Indeed, in a 1969 decision, the Supreme Court upheld the free speech rights of a young Black man who was participating in a rally against police brutality and had used insulting, threatening rhetoric, explaining that 鈥淸t]he language used in the political arena . . . is often vituperative [and] abusive.鈥 Similarly, in a 1982 decision, the Court protected the cursing, threatening language of a NAACP leader who was mobilizing a boycott of white merchants who engaged in racially discriminatory practices, stating that 鈥渟trong and effective extemporaneous rhetoric cannot be nicely channeled in purely dulcet phrases.鈥
The Supreme Court has repeatedly recognized that, especially in debates about public affairs, participants are likely to communicate in ways that are far from civil, and that such communications constitute the lifeblood of democracy, as well as being essential to individual liberty. In today鈥檚 contentious campus climate, many student activists have conveyed their objections to ideas of invited speakers, and to actions of university officials, as well as other students, in language that is harsh and insulting both in content and in the manner of delivery. We have all seen widely circulated videotapes of students boisterously interrupting remarks by speakers and university officials by shouting out insults, including vulgar and profane epithets. Could these students effectively convey their strongly held views through language that is constrained to be civil either in its content or its manner of delivery?
For persuasive reasons, the Supreme Court has consistently struck down restrictions on uncivil expression that it has characterized with a wide variety of negative adjectives, including: 鈥渁busive,鈥 鈥渃ontemptuous,鈥 鈥渃ontroversial,鈥 鈥渄isagreeable,鈥 鈥渄istasteful,鈥 鈥渉urtful,鈥 鈥渋nappropriate,鈥 鈥渋ndecent,鈥 鈥渋nsulting,鈥 鈥渕isguided,鈥 鈥渙ffensive,鈥 鈥渙pprobrious,鈥 鈥渙utrageous,鈥 鈥減atently offensive,鈥 鈥減rovocative,鈥 鈥渟currilous,鈥 鈥渟hocking,鈥 鈥渢hreatening,鈥 鈥渦nsettling,鈥 鈥渦psetting,鈥 and 鈥渧ulgar.鈥 The Court has concluded that, as a matter of principle, speakers may not be required to express themselves through more civil language. Moreover, the Court has concluded that, as a factual matter, speakers cannot adequately express themselves through such altered language.
Incivility and disrespect may very well constitute integral elements of the substantive message.
One important example is a landmark 1971 decision that arose during the U.S. engagement in the Vietnam War, Cohen v. California. The Court overturned the conviction of a young man, Paul Cohen, under a California statute that outlawed 鈥渄isturb[ing] the peace . . . of any . . .person . . . by . . . offensive conduct鈥 because, in a courthouse, he had worn a jacket bearing the message 鈥淔uck the Draft.鈥 As the Court recognized, 鈥淭he statute seeks to preserve an appropriately decorous atmosphere in the courthouse.鈥 At the time, the 鈥淔-word鈥 was considered extremely offensive and even shocking, to the extent that the Chief Justice indicated to Cohen鈥檚 lawyer that he should not utter the word during his Supreme Court argument, despite its central importance to the case. Nonetheless, the Court held that this statute violated Paul Cohen鈥檚 free speech right to convey his opposition to the Vietnam-era military draft through such strong language, despite the fact that it was deeply upsetting to many onlookers at the time. The Court based its ruling on several compelling rationales, all of which would doom any effort to enforce any requirement that communications must be conducted with civility.
First, the Cohen Court recognized the inherent vagueness of concepts such as 鈥渃ivility,鈥 鈥渙ffense,鈥 and 鈥渄ecorum,鈥 meaning that if the government were permitted to police individual expression pursuant to such vague 鈥渟tandards,鈥 the officials would wield essentially unfettered discretion. As the Court explained: 鈥渋t is . . . often true that one [person]鈥檚 vulgarity is another's lyric. Indeed, we think it is largely because governmental officials cannot make principled distinctions in this area that the Constitution leaves matters of taste and style so largely to the individual.鈥
Second, the Cohen Court recognized that freedom of speech shields an individual鈥檚 right to convey emotions, as well as ideas, and that therefore we each have the right to choose the content and manner of our communications accordingly. For example, if a speaker seeks to express outrage, she is likely to do so with outraged 鈥 and perhaps outrageous 鈥 language. As the Court elaborated:
[M]uch linguistic expression serves a dual communicative function: it conveys not only ideas capable of relatively precise, detached explication, but otherwise inexpressible emotions as well. In fact, words are often chosen as much for their emotive as their cognitive force. We cannot sanction the view that the Constitution, while solicitous of the cognitive content of individual speech, has little or no regard for that emotive function which, practically speaking, may often be the more important element of the overall message sought to be communicated.
Finally, the Court in effect paraphrased Marshall McLuhan鈥檚 famous aphorism that 鈥渢he medium is the message.鈥 It explained: 鈥淸W]e cannot indulge the facile assumption that one can forbid particular words without also running a substantial risk of suppressing ideas in the process. Indeed, governments might soon seize upon the censorship of particular words as a convenient guise for banning the expression of unpopular views.鈥
[LISTEN: Robert Corn-Revere reads Cohen v. California on 果冻传媒app官方鈥檚 鈥淔ree Speech Out Loud鈥 podcast.]
Given the inherent vagueness of the concept of 鈥渃ivility,鈥 and the resulting discretion it vests in enforcing authorities, the enforcement will be at best arbitrary and unpredictable, and at worst discriminatory, targeting disfavored speakers or ideas. Consistent with historic patterns, authorities are likely to enforce any such discretionary standard in accordance with their own subjective values, or those of powerful interest groups. It was no coincidence that Paul Cohen鈥檚 allegedly 鈥渙ffensive鈥 language, which purportedly 鈥渄isturbed the peace鈥 of onlookers, conveyed a controversial, critical view about the government鈥檚 Vietnam War policies. In today鈥檚 context, any civility code would no doubt be enforced against people who are protesting current government policies and actions, ranging from police practices to pandemic measures. Similarly, campus officials would likely enforce such codes against critics of their policies. On all sides of controversial issues, individuals with strong views are unlikely to confine their communications to those that other people, including officials, consider civil 鈥 nor should they be required to do so.
Greg: Civility is one of those words that officials, politicians, and university presidents tend to throw around as if it trumps freedom of speech by its very nature. But I find this assertion quite strange, and even sometimes disingenuous. No values are likely conceived of in LESS universal ways than 鈥減oliteness鈥 and 鈥渃ivility,鈥 and even within a single society, norms related to these values differ depending on one鈥檚 economic class, gender, region, and upbringing.
Appeals to 鈥渃ivility鈥 in attempts to censor really do cut all ways.
International travel can quickly disabuse people of the idea that civility norms are universal. As my Russian refugee father liked to say, 鈥渋f you come to another country and expect them to play by YOUR norms, you are acting like hick.鈥 The norms of politeness embraced by my Russian father and my British mother could not have been more different. And this brings us back once again to the brilliant John Stuart Mill, who noted in 鈥淥n Liberty鈥 that civility tends to be defined by those in power or in the ruling class. Therefore they鈥檙e quick to judge dissenting opinions, even if expressed politely, as inherently uncivil, but tend to see emotional, strident, or otherwise uncivil speech on their own side as righteous rage.
With regard to what is commonly meant by intemperate discussion, namely invective, sarcasm, personality, and the like, the denunciation of these weapons would deserve more sympathy if it were ever proposed to interdict them equally to both sides; but it is only desired to restrain the employment of them against the prevailing opinion: against the unprevailing they may not only be used without general disapproval, but will be likely to obtain for him who uses them the praise of honest zeal and righteous indignation.
The idea that there can be a single norm of civility in a country as profoundly diverse as the United States is bizarre. I believe that people graduating from elite universities can come to believe this only because most universities today have a fairly politically homogeneous professoriate, an even-more-homogenous administration, and, at schools like Harvard, a surprisingly homogenous student body. We have also become more class-segregated as a society over the past several decades, and elite universities tend to have a disproportionate number of students from the upper one percent of the economic distribution. This can lead to the classic phenomenon of upper-class people thinking that people of lower socioeconomic status are 鈥渦ncivil鈥 without seeming to realize that people of lower socioeconomic status quite intentionally disregard upper-class norms around civility and politeness to signal their decency, honesty, integrity, and authenticity. We recognize this reality in folk idioms like 鈥渒eeping it real.鈥
Appeals to 鈥渃ivility鈥 in attempts to censor really do cut all ways. In November 2021, Duke University鈥檚 student government denied recognition to the group, FIRESupporting Israel, on the basis that the group had been 鈥渦ncivil鈥 in responding to one of its critics. On the other side of the issue, the Board of Trustees at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign rescinded a job offer to Steven Salaita in 2014 over 鈥渦ncivil鈥 tweets criticizing Israel. (In one of the more unfortunate cases FIREhas seen, Salaita did not find another job in academia, and,, was driving a school bus to make ends meet.)
Politeness is indeed a virtue, but is not the greatest of all virtues.
Now that I have problematized the idea of civility and shown how it can be, at best, hard to define, and, at worst, outright abused, I do think basic ideas of civility 鈥 such as hearing each other out, granting the benefit of the doubt, or otherwise engaging in argument and discussion with open mindedness, curiosity, and good faith 鈥 reflect very important social values. However, as I鈥檝e said for decades now, 鈥淧oliteness is indeed a virtue, but is not the greatest of all virtues, and ranks far below authenticity, sincerity, and honesty.鈥
Recent Articles
FIRE鈥檚 award-winning Newsdesk covers the free speech news you need to stay informed.